Silas Marner, George
Eliot
Reviewed
by Patrick McEvoy-Halston
- - - -
-
Haunting
Raveloe
June 2002
In George Eliot’s Silas Marner
(1861), the men at the Rainbow debate over whether or not there is a ghost at
the Warren stables. Further, they
weigh in on whether a ghost, even if it did exist, would want “ignorant folk”
to believe in it. With Silas’s
unnoticed entrance into the bar, and with his apparition-like countenance,
Eliot suggests that ghosts aren’t actually all that discriminating as to who
they want to believe in them—they just want to be remembered. Silas, of course, is not a ghost, but
“ghosts,” or presences associated with the past, do haunt many characters in
the text. And these ghosts, if
ignored, give every reason for people such as those at the Rainbow to be wary
of them. Raveloe is also inhabited
by an apparition from the future:
Eliot herself, as a narrative presence. But Eliot would rather embrace Raveloe than haunt it. In fact, her visit is evidence of the
continuing influence of old ways of thinking—of ghosts—on her own life. Knowing intimately the increasing
prospects for happiness moderns like her have in an age where seemingly anyone
can rise to success, and knowing how different her situation and beliefs that
sustain it are from those of the past, she is not be able to shake off the
feeling that she has earned punishment for being unfaithful to her
heritage. In her unfaithfulness,
she is like her character Godrey Cass.
But perhaps—her vicious attack on him notwithstanding—Eliot is more like
the diabolically cunning and daring Dunstan, in imagining though her creation Silas Marner a stratagem for appeasing
the ancestral ghosts. By showing
both that she has not forgotten them and that she believes they must be
remembered—lest the present prove degenerate—Eliot placates internal
persecutors—but only so as to buy time until she is ready to banish them from
her mind altogether! We look first
to signs of agitation in the narrator in a text otherwise crafted by a
sympathetic but judicious mind, for evidence that Eliot fears she is
blameworthy for being an egoistic, willful modern.
When
Mr. Macey argues “[a]s if ghos’es ’ud want to be believed in by anybody so
ignirant” (Eliot 54), Eliot, with Silas’s ghost-like appearance at the Rainbow,
is able to suggest otherwise, because his statement could be contradicted by
experience. Experience, often in
the form of surprising, sudden, and dramatic changes to everyday life, is most
often used by Eliot to show how unpredictable nature is. Eliot’s conception of nature likely
strikes us as realistic for defining it as a force of persistent, aggressive
change. In Raveloe, or with
simple, reclusive people such as Silas, Eliot shows us that because “life [is]
[. . .] breathed on variously by multitudinous currents, from the winds of
heaven to the thoughts of men[,] [. . .] [which] are for ever moving and
crossing each other, with incalculable results” (23), neither the town nor its
inhabitants can long hold life or nature at bay. Realistic-seeming, too, is Eliot’s characterization of
systems or codes of thought as ideologies particular to a person or people at a
particular time and place. She
treats those who cling to regular and patterned ways of thinking with sympathy,
but in general shows rigid ways of thinking as imposing a form onto reality
which Reality either subverts at their user’s expense (as with Silas and his
ritual of leaving his door unlocked), or which encloses their users in
walled-in misery (as is the case with Nancy’s “unalterable little code[s]”
[156]).
Yet despite this tendency, she herself expresses a tenuous-seeming
maxim in the text, namely, that burglars are dull-minded, which she insists is
almost always true (39).
Furthermore, Silas Marner is
itself a rhetorical argument for judging the degree to which people are
rewarded and punished in life as depending entirely on how selfishly they
behave. It advances the same sort
of argument we often actually expect to see in a fairy tale, and it reflects a
world-view which Dunstan—the character Eliot makes a skeleton of—“deprecate[s]”
(74).
Eliot is concerned to show how Godrey,
Dunstan, and Silas think of themselves and how they fare in life. Godrey, at book’s end, has been both
punished and rewarded. He is
admonished in the text for not having the “moral courage” to own up to his
marriage to Molly to Nancy. Yet
not informing Nancy did not prevent the marriage, nor did it entirely ruin his
prospects for happiness: he fails
to make claim to Eppie, but clearly has found happiness in marriage. With “tenderness,” he says to Nancy
(175), “I got you in spite of all [,] [. . .] and yet I’ve been
grumbling and uneasy because I hadn’t something else” (175), adding, “as if I
deserved it” (175). Godrey’s
brother Dunstan is judged by Eliot for his demoniac cleverness, and is punished
more severely; for whereas Godrey at least had been modest enough to think
himself deserving of punishment, Dunstan extorts his brother and preys upon his
neighbors without any self-reproach.
To be rewarded with an entirely happy present, and with promising future
prospects, according to the logic of Silas
Marner, demands the “humble sort of acquiescence in what was held to be
good” (142) that Silas has.
Eliot,
who discerns when the landlord, for example, uses “analogical logic” (54),
clearly knows and believes that reflection can help one avoid mistaking norms
or habits of thought for universally valid truths. Reflecting on “[p]oor Marner” (14), she tells us that “[t]o
people accustomed to reason about the forms in which their religious feeling
has incorporated itself, it is difficult to enter into that simple, untaught
state of mind in which the form and the feeling have never been severed by an
act of reflection” (14). According
to psychoanalyst Stanley Greenspan, however, even those used to reasoning
things out and reflecting before acting, may find that in certain circumstances
they are unable to make use of these higher-order thinking processes. He writes:
The emotional guides to our thinking can also lead us astray during
extreme states of anxiety, depression, fear, anger, or the like. At such times our emotions become so
overwhelming that we are unable to fine-tune our ideas. Thoughts become polarized, rigid,
fixed, while inflexible beliefs dominate the mind. (34)
Greenspan,
who believes that each of our sensory perceptions is “[labelled] by [. . .]
both its physical properties [. . .] and by the emotional qualities we connect
with it” (21), and that abstractions are created by “fus[ing] various emotional
experiences into a single, integrated concept” (26), would disagree with
Eliot’s contention that reflection severs
form from feeling; to him, reflection, instead, helps us “modulate our
emotions” (22). And since even
highly abstract concepts like religion are actually at-the-core constituted
by emotions (27), the reasoning philosopher no less than the untaught and
simple is able to—or should ever really want to—exempt herself from emotional
influence. Those who seek pure exemption,
in fact—and so not just those overrun by base desires—are exactly those to be
expected to suffer from extreme lapses of self-control, for their flight no
doubt owes to their inexperience in successfully managing what are, of course, inevitable emotional upsets.
Perhaps
the reason that Eliot, then—at least with the dispersal of rewards and
punishments is concerned—suddenly conceives of nature as predictable and
orderly, that it ensures that there are, to Dunstan’s huge misfortune,
“unpleasant consequences” to people’s actions (73), when otherwise nature is
vicarious and unfathomable, is because Eliot herself, with this matter, has not
yet managed to entirely free herself from that simple way of thinking too
bonded to emotional arousal to enable reflective thought. That is, while writing, when she brings
to mind clear examples of egoism, of people’s intention to satisfy themselves,
feeling guilty for her own superior intelligence and
success she becomes so agitated she cannot manage that controlled, calibrated
state of mind required to notice, and therefore be capable of altering, her
inclination to associate ambition with hubris, and see vengeance visited upon
all guilty trespassers.
Eliot, we know, does not always distinguish herself from “simpletons”;
she frequently tells us—often including all humanity in her sweeping
generalizations—that we all share some of the mental habits of the simple and
honest members of the Raveloe community.
But suspiciously, the exceptions—those such as William Dane and Dunstan
Cass, who consider themselves exceptional, and who duly expect status and
riches—are also those whose gains she insists on characterizing as
ill-gotten. William, whom his
peers see as being “so dazzled by his own light as to hold himself wiser than
his teachers” (10), displaces Silas as a revered brother with a plot that
involves stealing from the deacon.
Dunstan, who “swaggers” (34), who is always on the lookout “to take [. .
.] someone in” (34), refers to Silas as an “old staring simpleton” (39). William and Dunstan are youngsters who
not only disrespect their elders—the teachers, with William; the elderly, with
Dunstan—but are indifferent to their fates once they have left them behind them
in pursuit of further “petty egoistic” (156) acquisitions. Dunstan possesses a singular ability to
arouse Eliot. Eliot, who seems to
find every way to find virtue in the simplest of minds, finds none at all when
she estimates Dunstan’s dull. But
is this really how she thinks of
him? We note how she attaches this
label just after his dismissing Silas as but an old simpleton. Further, while the sequence that has
him ride his horse to death and burglar Silas shows him as an impulse-driven,
unthinking fool, previously Dunstan not only showed considerable cunning in his
mastery over his brother but also showed his ability to master his
emotions. Considering that Eliot
characterizes Dunstan’s manipulation of Godrey so that it seems much more
diabolically clever than miscreant but otherwise dull, spite and vengeance, not
reasoned fair commentary, clearly is moving her pen here.
Previously
Eliot showed Dunstan as a risk-taker, but a thoughtful and intelligent one,
emphasizing his own self-control and Godrey’s lack thereof. While Godrey succumbs to a “movement of
compunction [. . .] which was a blight on his life,” it is Dunstan who sees “in
his brother’s degrading marriage the means of gratifying at once his jealous
hate and his cupidity” (31), and seizes upon his opportunity. Godrey prefers to intimidate rather
than reason with his brother.
Godrey, “mastered by [. . .] fear,” would flog [Dunstan] [. . .] within
an inch of his life” (29).
Dunstan, in contrast, maintains, even while under physical threat from
threat, “an air of unconcern” (29).
His impressive insouciance owes to having sufficient insight into his
brother’s ways that he can simply “wait” (29) for Godrey to stop resisting, and
then lead him to accept his terms.
If Eliot was to make a fair assessment of Dunstan’s intelligence and
impulse control at this point in the narrative, she really could do no better
than to suggest, as Godrey does, that he could have “more sharpness” (27). But even in this she would be in error,
because one of Dunstans’s goals—unfortunate as it surely is—is to agitate his
brother as much as possible. He
braves a trial, risks error (or “oversho[oting] his mark” [27]), but thereby
better knows just how well he has caught his brother out. Ultimately, we note, Godrey
acquiesces. Dunstan accomplishes
his goal, and need not fear Godrey. But Dunstan is not,
however, safe from Eliot; and it is
she, incapable of the restraint that even Godrey manages, who ultimately
“knock[s] [. . .] [Dunstan] down” (28).
What
Dunstan in particular represents to Eliot is someone who “forsake[s] a decent craft
that he may pursue the gentilities of a profession to which nature never called
him” (74). Dunstan, the second
son, lives a gentry-life of drink, horseriding, and leisure, and has his elder
brother contemplate the consequences of becoming a soldier (28). In his presumption, Dunstan is similar
to William Dane, who, though favored, is not looked upon with quite the
reverence as those thought selected by God (such as Silas) for a special
purpose are. As with Dunstan,
William, when he devises means to benefit at Silas’s expense, betrays the bond
that ought to exist between brothers, and both of them can be imagined as
similar in nature to Eliot and her contemporaries. Mid-Victorians, as with Dunstan, and as with later born
sons, rather than having clear roles and identities thrust upon them, have
instead the nebulous freedom to shape their fates themselves. Elder sons have an obvious link to the
past in that they would—as with Godrey—“come into the land someday” (24). They are more easily imagined—again, as
with Godrey (and as Eliot herself imagines him)—“as having an essentially
domestic nature” (31), and are thus not subject (as Eliot imagines Dunstan) to
wanderlust. Eliot, like Dunstan
and William, possesses the intelligence to, if she should desire, manipulate
those about her for her own benefit.
Moreover, they all have sufficient will and self-confidence to accept
the risks involved in pursuing ambitious goals. In a complex, modern, ever-changing society, this degree of
intelligence and will would be necessary, not just to ably succeed but simply
to meaningfully participate, and would have been imagined by Eliot and her
contemporaries the norm for their age.
But perhaps the habitual association of this sort of intelligence as
egoistic and self-serving—as “bad”—afflicts people like Eliot sufficiently that
it still leads to attempts at penance, variant enough to include the likes of
Eliot’s attempt to punish her likeness in her writing, and necessitates efforts
to exonerate themselves from charges they belong to a dangerously degenerate
age far removed in purity from the “honest[y] [belonging to] [. . .] their
ancestors” (20).
We
know that Eliot is concerned to show how intrusive past events can be upon our
present existence. Eliot tells us
that Nancy “filled the vacant moments by living inwardly, over and over again,
through all her remembered experience” (154), an experience Eliot characterizes
as a “morbid habit of mind” (154).
And with Godrey, Eliot shows us someone who cannot, simply by changing
his patterns of thinking, free himself from torment. For even if Godrey was, with the gracious assistance of
time, to forget his past, the past has
not chosen to forget or forgive him!
Eliot conjures up Molly as a revenant, as an embodied ghost who returns
from the dead to punish Godrey.
The passage of time, forgetfulness, actually works to Molly’s advantage,
for she wants nothing more than to catch Godrey just when he feels safe enough
from harm to venture out to pursue a relationship with Nancy. Eliot wishes Godrey had the moral
courage to tell Nancy about his marriage to Molly earlier than he in fact does,
but considering it is difficult to believe Eliot imagines this would not have
ruined his chances with her, using his confession
of wrongfulness toward Molly to express the wrongfulness of her own neglect of her past would seem
untenable, a false-confession—a lie.
Eliot is, however, trying to
demonstrate to internal persecutors, to ghosts nesting in her mind, that with Silas Marner she is remembering her
forefathers—her “neighbors” from the past—and that she not only values them
but, given the chance, would readily stand up for them.
Eliot
defends the Raveloe inhabitants both through subtle plot contrivances and
through impassioned narrative rants.
The members of the Raveloe community are described as simple and honest,
but at times, also as vengeful and barbaric. At the beginning of Eliot’s account, it is only fear, born
of superstition, which prevents Silas “from the persecution that his
singularities might have drawn upon him” (9). And near book’s end, Silas’s isolation helps protect Eppie
from “the lowering influences of [. . .] village talk and habits” (146). The result is that, since we never do
witness their persecution of Silas, nor do we see Eppie grow into anything
other than a pure child, we are most likely to associate the typical Raveloean
with the benevolent Dolly. Eliot
also has the chance to actively defend Nancy (apparently from some of the
readers she has “invited along”) when she seeks to reprove “grammatically fair
ones,” who cannot fathom how her “feelings can at all resemble theirs”
(93). And Eliot sometimes even
sounds like a proud member of the Raveloe community, especially when she
mimics, with her diatribe against those who seek more than they were by nature
ordained to possess, the Raveloean hatred for those who “wish to be better than
the ‘common run’” (80).
With
Silas Marner, Eliot proves to herself she is more the favored who embraces the
past than a truant in mind to disparage it. As with Eppie’s soothing remarks to her father when he fears
he may lose her upon marriage, that he is not so much losing a daughter as
gaining a son, Eliot tells herself that as a successful modern writer she is
not detaching herself from the norms of her forefather but rather attaching,
with a supposed respect for old folkways in her writing, a new age to her
own. So doing, she hopes to
replace her habitual conception of those “who ha[ve] more cunning than honest
folks [. . .] [not using] that cunning in a neighbourly way” (77), with her
preferred sense that “mind[s] [. . . ] of extraordinary acuteness must
necessarily contemplate the doings of their fallible fellow-men” (102). She hopes, as proved true with Eppie,
having placated her “relations,” she might better enjoy her own refinement and
true difference.
It
is even possible that Eliot may not, at heart, truly respect her
forefathers. Indeed, there are
signs in the text that she thinks the poverty of “ordinary farmers” (68)—the prototypical inhabitant of our
pastoral past—a condition they both could and should have freed themselves from. We feel this when she draws our attention to how similar in
nature the Raveloe farmers are to Squire Cass, remarking that because they have
“slouched their way through life with a consciousness of being in the vicinity
of their ‘betters,’ [they] want that self-possession and authoritativeness of
voice and carriage which belong[s] to a man who thought of superiors as remote
existences” (68). Perhaps for
Eliot, Raveloe is akin to the brown pot Silas keeps by his hearth: it is be kept and tended to only while
its mistreatment might “bruise [her] [. . .] roots” (142)—that is, while its
removal or replacement would disturb her.
But just as Silas might one day come to experience his precious
relic—the last remaining piece at book’s end of his dwelling’s old
furnishings—as but a plain old pot he’s too long kept near his side, Eliot
might come to see Raveloe—or, rather, the composite of place, time, and people
Raveloe represents—as fear-inhibited and irrelevant, and forget now exactly why
she once placed so much interest in it.
Considering Eliot’s previous loving sentiment, thoughts, and words, this
would be a considerable betrayal of her forefathers, but as she herself tells
us, “language is a stream that is almost sure to smack of a mingled soil” (78).
Work Cited
Eliot, George. Silas
Marner. Toronto: Penguin Books, 1996. Print.
Greenspan,
Stanley. Growth of the Mind: And the Endangered Origins of Intelligence. New York: Addison-Wesley, 1997. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment