Robinson
Crusoe,
Daniel Defoe; Gulliver’s Travels,
Jonathon Swift
Reviewed by Patrick McEvoy-Halston
- - - - -
Splendid Isolation and Cruel Returns
Robinson Crusoe’s and Gulliver’s true desires, in
Daniel Defoe’s Robinson Crusoe and
Jonathon Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels
November 2004
Does
Robinson Crusoe, in Daniel Defoe’s Robinson
Crusoe, really believe he should have “settle[d] at home according to [his]
Father’s Desire[s]” (7)? Since the
text shows he deemed living at home a life of captivity and that he found the
island he was stranded on very fulfilling, it’s clear he’s suffering from
considerable self-deception here.
Does Gulliver, in Jonathon Swift’s Gulliver’s
Travels, really believe it was his misfortune that “Fortune, [his] [. . .]
perpetual Enemy” prevented him from “pass[ing] the rest of his life among these
admirable Houyhnhnms” (240)? Since he occupies himself much more
with the affairs of his enemies than he does the accomplishments of friends, he
clearly does not. For him as well,
that is, the ostensible worst option is really the vastly preferred choice; for
even if to gods, servitude is apparently only good if it empowers cruelty upon
lesser mortals upon your return home.
Allow me to elaborate.
It
is hard to argue that Crusoe comes to
regret his decision to leave his father, for just as soon as he “broke loose”
(8) from him he ostensibly knew right away what a colossal mistake it was to
set out on his own. In fact,
within the very same paragraph in which he broke loose he tells us he “began
now seriously to reflect upon what [he] [. . .] had done, and how justly [he]
[. . .] was overtaken by the Judgment of Heaven for [his] [. . .] wicked
[decision to] leav[e] [his] [. . .] Father’s house, and [to] abandon [his] [. .
.] Duty” (9). Crusoe’s not
conveying any happiness or
exhilaration upon breaking free is puzzling. Surely he must have felt somewhat elated afterwards,
experienced some kind of victory-related rush—why not relate this feeling? Why in his account does he depict no
moment, in public or in private, of how he celebrated his release? Maybe there wasn’t any such moment—but
I highly suspect there was, only in recounting his departure from his father he
felt compelled to avoid conveying the pleasure he experienced in both disobeying
his father and in finally starting upon a self-willed life. Damning criticism of one’s parents is
never an easy thing to just lay down. Most times, our ego/superego will in
fact not stand for it, and will afflict us with the likes of castration anxiety
or fears of abandonment should we insist on doing so. Crusoe certainly avoids overtly criticizing his father in
his account—he describes him, rather, very appreciatively. We are told that his father was “a wise
and grave man, [who] gave [him] [. . .] serious and excellent Counsel” (5),
that his father was affectionate—“he press’d me earnestly, and in the most
affectionate manner, not to play the young Man”—and sincere—his “Tears r[an]
down his Face very plentifully” (7).
He would deter his son from pursuing the life he wants to pursue, but
for generous reasons: he wants his
son to “slide[e] gently thro’ the World, and sensibly tasting the Sweets of
living, without the bitter” (7).
Essentially, he wants for his son what the speaker of Lady Mary Chudleigh’s
“The Resolve” wants for herself, to be “happy in [his] [. . .] humble state”
(21). Crusoe dares say he “broke
free,” but largely avoids assessing his former life so he could not but admit
to himself that it was the obvious—a cage—he had succeeded in breaking free
from. And when he departs, Crusoe
attends only to his own character flaws.
We learn that he was “obstinately deaf to all Proposals” (Defoe 8), and
that he “consulted neither Father or Mother [about his departure] [. . .]; but
left them to hear of it as they might, without asking God’s blessing, or my
Father’s, without any Consideration of Circumstances or Consequences, and in an
ill Hour” (9).
His
father offers him a life where he “was under no Necessity of seeking [his] [. .
.] Bread” (7). He would be fed; he
would be safe. He would know a
routine life, full of happiness, but void of excitement. He would never know from his own
experience if the one his father presented him with was the best available, but
his father tells him he would still know from everyone envying him (6). We might wonder, however, if everyone
really would envy a man who could never find his way to “leave [his] [. . .]
Father’s house” (9). Perhaps a
good number might actually think that such a man, never knowing what it feels
like to live on your own, lived but a posher one one would force upon a slave.
I
suspect Crusoe thought as much but was fearful of directly lambasting his
father’s intention to keep him rooted in place. However, if we accept Norman Holland argument that “unsavory
wishful fantasies” are reworked in fiction so that they are “consciously
satisfying [to] [. . .] the ego and unconsciously satisfying to the deep wishes
being acted out by the literary work” (104), we find that he does convey his
anger at this father elsewhere in his account.
Crusoe
allowed for some textual padding, for some time to lapse, before making clear
what it is about people and places that draws him to break free from them—not
much, though, for just twenty pages after his departure he recounts for us how
he narrowly avoided living a life of captivity. A Moorish captain captures him at sea, admires him (he
thought him valuable property for he was “young and nimble and fit for his
Business” [Defoe 18]), and decides to keep him as his servant. Because he is being compelled to live
the life of a domestic, forever “look[ing] after his little Garden,” tending to
“his House” and “his Ship,” Crusoe decides his situation “could not be worse”
(18). He would be “commanded” and
“order’d” (30) about. He therefore
“meditated nothing but [his] [. . .] Escape” (18), for he “was resolved to have
[his] [. . .] Liberty” (21). Being
a valuable slave, he might have been well kept, but what bothers Crusoe is that
someone else is determining his
life. He despises the idea of
orbiting around someone else, of being someone who lives to satisfy other people’s needs. Though
he does conceive of the Moorish captain as an agent of (his father’s) prophecy
(28), he also makes clear that the Moor is a tyrant, and that his thoughts of
liberation are fully justified.
But if he finds living a provisioning but kept domestic life so odious
here, we should understand the true mover behind his leaving his father, not
wanderlust, but rather the staunch refusal of the caging life. He was
capable of an honest assessment of such a life, but could manage it only where
his honesty would not look to insult or condemn his father.
Crusoe,
however, never admits to being right in disobeying his father. The way in which Gulliver relates to
his Houyhnhnm masters is about how he would admit he ought to have attended to
him. The Houyhnhnms and Crusoe’s
father are similar to one another, valuing much the same things—“Temperance, Industry, Exercise, and Cleanliness”
(251) by the Houyhnhnms, and “Temperance, Moderation, Quietness, [and] [. . .]
Health” (6) by Crusoe’s father.
However, unlike Crusoe, Gulliver ostensibly is never interested in
breaking free from wise fathers, but rather in spending the whole of his life
amongst his new-found betters. He
tells us he was so eager to learn the Houyhnhnms’ ways that he “never presumed
to speak, except in answer to a Question; and then [he] [. . .] did it with
inward Regret, because it was a Loss of so much Time for improving” (259)
himself. He admires how their
young do exactly as their parents bid:
“[Y]oung Couple[s] meet and are joined, merely because it is the
Determination of their Parents and Friends: It is what they see done every Day; and they look upon it as
one of the necessary Actions in a reasonable Being” (250). He takes pleasure in being their
servant, appreciates their reasoning nature, their evident superiority to him,
and agrees to follow their directions to the best of his ability. Therefore, though he is commanded and
ordered about (e.g., “my master commanded me silence” [2417]), he acknowledges
no reason for complaint.
Gulliver
believes he will live a life of relative peace and tranquility—the sort of life
Crusoe’s father offers Crusoe. But
“In the Midst of all this Happiness, when [he] [. . .] looked upon [himself] [.
. .] to be fully settled for Life” (260), he learns that he must depart the
island. He tells us he was
devastated by the news—“I was struck with the utmost Grief and Despair at my
Master’s Discourse; and being unable to support the Agonies I was under, I fell
into a Swoon at his Feet” (262)—and upon later recounting it, damns Fortune for
the terrible turn. But if Fortune
was indeed responsible, she deserved better than that from him, for Gulliver really wanted to leave, only this
wasn’t something he could readily own up to.
Gulliver
becomes a servant, and we hear of how he obeys orders and commands—but I am not
arguing that like Crusoe he wanted to depart to be free from captivity. Rather, I think he was ready to leave
the Houyhnhnms because he was done with them, they had served their
purpose, and had nothing more to offer.
The Houyhnhnms had heard all of his complaints concerning the European
culture he loathed, validated his surly opinion of it, and provided him with
justification for thinking himself superior to the rest of the Yahoos. This done it was time to return home to
be within easy reach of said Yahoos, whom he could now subjugate with less
worry of incurring any nagging self-reproach.
The
Houyhnhnms evict Gulliver from their island for fear that, however unlikely, he
could yet still lead a revolt.
They ultimately judge that Gulliver, still a Yahoo, is not to be
trusted—and they are right in this, he isn’t. He quite readily misleads his readers, for instance. Though he claimed he was primarily
interested in the Houyhnhnms, and though he does provide us with “some account
of the manner and customs of” those “which it was indeed [his] [. . .]
principal Study to learn” (249), he actually ends up spending the best part of
his account detailing European life
and manners. He says he was
compelled to provide this information to the Houyhnhnms. His master was eager to be informed of
“the whole State of Europe,” “often
desiring fuller Satisfaction,” and his master’s immense desire (an example of
excess in a Houyhnhnm?) ostensibly accounts for why the discussion of European
life possibly seemed—for us—“a Fund
of Conversation not to be exhausted” (228). He tells us he would rather have kept quiet and studied
their ways, but since no one compelled him to relate all of these details to
“us,” he clearly is much more interested in criticizing his previous home than
in detailing the various what-nots of Houyhnhnms’ oh-so-compelling how-tos.
Note how
even when establishing what his life amongst the Houyhnhnms was like he does so
in a way which has us actually mostly attending to European life:
I
enjoyed perfect Health of Body, and Tranquillity of Mind; I did not feel the
Treachery or Inconstancy of a Friend, nor the Injuries of a secret or open
Enemy. I had no Occasion of
bribing, flattering or pimping, to procure the Favor of any great Man, or of
his Minion. I wanted no Fence
against Fraud or Oppression: Here
was neither Physician to destroy my Body, nor Lawyer to ruin my Fortune: No Informer to watch my Words and
Actions, or forge Accusations against me for Hire; Here were no Gibers,
Censurers, Backbiters, Pickpockets, Highwaymen, House-breakers, Attorneys,
Bawds, Buffoons, Gamesters, Politicians, Wits, Spleneticks, tedious Talkers,
Controvertists, Ravishers, Murderers, Robbers, Virtuoso’s; no Leaders or
Followers of Party and Faction; no Encouragers to Vice, by Seducement or
Examples: No Dungeon, Axes,
Gibbets, Whipping-posts, or Pillories; No cheating Shopkeepers or
Mechanicks: No Pride, Vanity or
Affectation: No Fops, Bullies,
Drunkards, strolling Whores, or Poxes:
No ranting, lewd, expensive Wives:
No stupid, proud Pedants:
No importunate, over-bearing, quarrelsome, noisy, roaring, empty,
conceited, swearing Companions: No
Scoundrels, raised from the Dust upon the Merit of their Vices; or Nobility
thrown into it on account of their Virtues: No Lords, Fiddlers, Judges or Dancing-masters (258-59).
Obviously,
if this passage reflects how he experienced life amongst the Houyhnhnms,
European life was very much on his mind while amongst them. And, in this passage at least, the
outpouring of details, of complaint, cannot be accounted for by Houyhnhnms’
demand for fuller satisfaction.
Since
the text shows that Gulliver enjoyed all his complaining, we should not think
he was prepared to leave it all behind him. Rather, we should ask ourselves if what he really wanted was
for his natural inclination to believe himself superior to find sanction from
some higher power, noting that the Houyhnhnms, so “orderly and rational, so
acute and judicious” (211), are also so
right to help him out with this.
Though they judge Gulliver a Yahoo, they deem him unique for his
race—unlike other Yahoos, he, much like a Houyhnhnm, is “Teachable, Civil and
Clean” (218). Why would he want
that? Because, unfortunately, he
is sadist who wants to bully people, but needs authorizing validation to make
his inclination sound rather than cruel.
When he returns home, we note his domineering ways: the first thing he recounts for us is
how quickly and unsparingly he established order in his household. He is disgusted by his family, and will
not let them near him. He abuses
us readers as well. After he explains
how much his family disgusted him, he speaks to his “gentle Reader” (272). The
Longman Anthology of British Literature teaches gentle students that
Gulliver must be being ironic here, for his “‘gentle readers must be Yahoos”
(2443). But Longman is not quite
on the mark here, for not ironic or playful, Gulliver is here simply being
cruel: he insinuates that his
readers, who very likely would prefer to understand themselves gentle /
genteel, are in truth foul. As we
observe from the way he treats his family, Yahoos aren’t worth being civil to,
and cannot be effectively handled civilly in any case. They are savages that need to have
their savagery pointed out to them (in-between beatings, very likely) so they
will know improvement, and just possibly, seek it out, however much beside the
point.
There
are other times where he expresses his dismay at, and his dislike for, his
readers. When he writes, “[h]aving
already lived three Years in this Country, the Reader I suppose will expect,
that I should, like other Travelers, give him some Account of the Manner and
Customs of its Inhabitants” (249), we sense him sighing, even sneering, at our
expectations. His being resigned
to placate us suggests he deems us “the most unteachable of all Animals, [with]
[our] [. . .] Capacities never reaching higher than to draw or carry Burthens”
(248). Elsewhere he
insinuates that his readers—so unlike the Houyhnhnms—are largely uncaring and
completely self-interested: “This is enough to say upon the Subject of my Dyet,
wherewith other Travelers fill their books, as if the Readers were personally
concerned, whether we fare well or ill” (217).
It is
useful to think of Gulliver as being literally, physically off-putting in how he treats
his readers, for perhaps Gulliver prefers to imagine us at a distance to avoid
any reoccurrence of the physical revulsion he experienced when his wife
embraced him upon his return home.
However, it is of course more appropriate to look to Crusoe for an account of the pleasure
had from commanding a wide-birth of physical space. One of Crusoe’s first actions on the island is to build a
“Fortification” (59). But though
he fears hostile engagements with savages, none occur until many years go
by. In the meantime, he extends
his knowledge of the island, the breadth of his domain. He develops a country bower and grows
crops. Incrementally he
“prepare[s] more [and more] land” (101).
The expansion of his domain expands his sense of himself, until finally,
as the scholar Pat Rogers argues, “we should consider Crusoe’s increasing
readiness to see himself as ‘Governour’ [. . .] as [him feeling] the monarch of
all he surveys” (44).
Crusoe
certainly enjoys being “a monarch.”
He tells us, “I descended a little on the side of that delicious vale,
surveying it with a secret kind of pleasure [. . .] to think that this was all
my own, that I was king and lord of all this country indefeasibly, and had a
right of possession; and if I could convey it, I might have it in inheritance
as completely as any lord of a mannor in England” (Defoe 99). Rogers argues that Crusoe was indeed
having so much indulgent fun that “it is hard not to feel that Defoe was
indulging at some level in a fantasy of himself as colonial proprietor” (45).
Michael
Boardman argues that “[t]he situation of exile, even the peace that comes form
his mastering of nature, might seem less than ideal as a scene for the agonics
of repentance” (56). I concur, and
believe we should wonder just how much of even his initial despair owed to a
concern to not show his father up.
His father told him to avoid the “secret burning Lust of Ambition”
(Defoe 7) and prophesized that “if he goes abroad he will be the miserablest
Wretch that was ever born” (8); and Crusoe felt the need to prove his father
right, insisting to the forefront of his consciousness that the island was his
despair, while relaxing to his default—ready enjoyment of the island—when the
risen guilt had been dealt with.
But even when he despairs, the text actually works against its summing up his overall experience of exile. For example, when he finishes listing
the “Evil” and “Good” things about life on the island, he concludes that “here
was an undoubted Testimony, that there was scarce any Condition in the World so
miserable, but there was something Negative
or something Positive to be thankful
for in it” (58). Yet when we look
at the list we notice that far more is written under the Good side than under
the Evil side of the ledger—it is not
suitable for a “some-of-one-some-of-the-other” sum-up. This discrepancy is especially
significant since, unlike a listing of debits and credits, the Good side is
written in response to that put under the Evil side. That is, the weight of his interest resides in countering
what he’d put down on the ledger’s damning left-hand side.
As his
account proceeds other things accrue to him that also ought fairly to be put on
the Good side, if only he could manage it. Remarkably, for instance, he apparently loses his
inclination to wander. Even
though, after exploring the rest of the island, he admits he “had pitch’d upon
a Place to fix [his] [. . .] Abode, which was by far the worst Part of the
Country” (100), he decides he would not “by any Means [. . .] remove” (101). Hearing this, we have further cause to
wonder if he ever really suffered
from wanderlust, that is, if perhaps he only felt the need to “run quite away”
(7-8) when his life was being determined for him. Crusoe also acquires wisdom. He tells us he learned that “we never see the true State of
our Condition, till it is illustrated to us by its Contraries; nor know how to
value what we enjoy, but by the want of it” (118). And from this statement we know of another thing he wouldn’t
but certainly ought to place under
the Good side of his ledger—specifically, that his father was clearly wrong to
deter him from setting out on his own.
We remember his father telling him he should live the middling life, for
that way he would “tast[e] the sweets of living without the bitter.” But Crusoe concludes that if one lives
without being “expos’d to [. . .] vicissitudes” (6), one cannot enjoy life, for
those who know only the good things in life would never know or “feel that they
are happy” (7). Crusoe decides
that the venturesome life, the life his father did not want him to lead,
actually lead him to know and therefore properly savor happiness.
Crusoe
individuates from his father on the island, a father, whose understanding of
what was best for his son was clearly limited. Though even as an older man Crusoe still persists in
believing he would have better off had he never left home, in his covert
challenges to his father’s benevolence and wisdom, in his written articulations
of the pleasures and awareness he took from a way of life his father would think
befouling, he establishes the evident rightness of his decision to set out on
his own. He is to be believed when
he tells us he “thought [he] liv’d really very happily in all things, except
that of Society” (122), and later when he tells us how “in [his] [. . .] twenty
third Year of residence in this Island, [. . .] [he] was so naturalized to the
Place, and to the Manner of Living, that could [. . .] [he] have but enjoy’d
the Certainty that no Savages would come to the Place to disturb [. . .] [him]
, [. . .] [he] could have been content to have capitulated for spending the
rest of [. . .] [his] Time there, even to the last Moment, till [. . .] [he]
had laid me down and dy’d, like the old Goat in the Cave” (152). For Crusoe had found for himself pretty
close to what the speaker of Anne Finch’s “The Petition for an Absolute
Retreat” desperately wanted, namely, “A sweet, but absolute retreat, / ‘Mongst
paths so lost, and trees so high, / That the world may ne’er invade” (3-5). Gulliver, on the other hand, since he
never convinces us he is more interested in the Houyhnhnms than he is in
criticizing European society, also never convinces us he wanted to leave it all
behind him. Rather, he shows
himself—as the speaker of Miss W—’s
“The Gentleman’s Study” assesses Jonathan Swift—just someone who
actually would rather “write of [. . .] odious men” (4) than “write of angels”
(1).
Works
Cited
Damrosch,
David ed. The Longman Anthology of
British Literature. New York:
Addison-Wesley,
1999.
Defoe,
Daniel. Robinson Crusoe. New York:
Oxford University Press, 2008.
Print.
Holland,
Norman. The Dynamics of Literary Response.
New York: Oxford University Press, 1968. Print.
Rogers,
Pat. Robinson Crusoe. London: George
Allen and Unwin, 1979. Print.
Swift,
Jonathon. Gulliver’s Travels. New
York: Oxford University Press, 2008. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment