Frankenstein, Mary Shelley; “Ode on a Grecian Urn,” John
Keats
Reviewed by Patrick McEvoy-Halston
- - - - -
Pleasure into Pain, Pain into Pleasure
Mary Shelley and John Keats’ Romantic Solution to
a Classic Problem, in Shelley’s Frankenstein
and Keat’s “Ode on a Grecian Urn”
November 2001
When I read the critiques
of Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein (1831
edition) and John Keats’ odes, especially his “Ode to a Grecian Urn,” I feel as
if I ought to ask myself if it is actually misleading to identify either of
them as Romantic, that is, as possessed of immoderate energy, as moved by a
desire to unsettle and change. Mary Shelley, wife of Percy Shelley,
daughter, as she told Percy on their first meeting, “of Godwin and Mary
[Wollestonecraft]” (37), is surely a
definitive Romantic writer, isn’t she? According to many, perhaps not so
much. Maurice Hindle, for instance, in the introduction to a Penguin
Classics’ edition of Frankenstein that he wrote with a wide audience in
mind—and whom we might thus expect to be hesitant to pre-judge the work for
readers potentially new to it—bluntly asserts that “its [Frankenstein’s] moral lesson that pride must have its fall should
be obvious to the most indifferent reader” (viii). He sees Frankenstein
as a first work which evidences her what-would-prove commendable life-long
preference for simple “domestic happiness and good friends,” of “moderate and
peaceful ambitions” (xlvi), not really
so much out of having herself known loss but out of respect for the “moderate
needs of the community” (xxxviii) and disdain for the “‘sexy’ lure of
scientific penetration” (xlvii).
The proud, self-absorbed, over-reaching hero appeals to the Romantic
spirit; a tale that subjugates him to the argument that it’s actually best to
remain in place, not so much. Hindle accepts as obvious (“[t]here seems
little doubt that [–]”) a judgment by P. D. Fleck that Frankenstein “contains in an imaginative form her criticism of [Percy] Shelley” (iv;
emphasis added). So that’s
it: Mary’s last name mislead me
into expecting her to focus on the Romantic engagement
with the life of a great but doomed man, when she rightly belongs in my mind’s
catalogue of authors and their works with the Classic, with, say, Samuel
Johnson and his “Vanity of Human Wishes,” that are primarily interested in judging such a life as immoderately
lead. John Keats—now he must be
a Romantic, for if not, who possibly?, just Bryon and Shelley? But
doesn’t Keats also provide a similar lesson to Johnson’s “Vanity of Human
Wishes”? Keats’ “conclusion” to his “Ode to a Grecian Urn, ” “‘Beauty is
truth, truth beauty,’—that is all / Ye know on earth, and all ye need to
know” (50), even if to instruct us as to what we should just stick to rather
than show what follows from having let ourselves go, still shares with “Vanity”
the concern to discourage waywardness.
And it is true that though some critics dispute the claim that the last
two moralizing lines truly represent Keats’ judgment, and though some hold that
the last two lines are out of sync with the rest of the poem—with some sensing
another voice here (perhaps it’s the urn speaking?)—for many and perhaps most,
it’s all Keats, all the way through.
However, from my own explorations of Frankenstein and “Ode to a Grecian Urn,”
I do not dispute that both authors moralize, nor that this moralizing can seem
so obvious to appear the point of their works. But because I consider the central and great life conflict
that between our right to pursue our own dreams—what we owe ourselves—and “the
disapproval or condemnation of significant others, such as parents” (Branden
63)—what they think we still owe them—and that the guilt and fear this
disapproval causes, because of its source, is overwhelming and near
unmanageable, to the point that it can still people in place for generations,
it is really no surprise that the parents’ (elders’) moralizing voice often
dominates these works, can appear the
point in these works: It
should, rather, be expected to, even in works whose overall impetus is very
much still contest and revolt, and does not by itself disqualify either of them
as Romantic. So long as there is a sense that the moralizing voice is
present so the writer can engage with it, find a way, perhaps, to triumph over
it, the work is a Romantic one. And Shelley and Keats are fighting, they are resisting
parental demands for them to let go their dreams, with both ending up finding
some solution to their parents’ claims upon them: Shelley, through embracing the monstrous; Keats, through
further immersion into his pain.
From the
very beginning of Frankenstein there are signs that
Shelley is not simply about to tell us
a moral tale, but rather is trying on
a moralizing voice, as if looking to resolve feelings of uncertainty towards
this voice, its message, while at the same time asking herself if it truly is
her own. If we are not too hasty to assume that simply because Shelley is
female (and thus cognizant, even at this early age, of the over-ambition
ostensibly peculiar to the male sex), and because the lesson we think she wants
to impart regards the dangers of Promethean-style scientific overreach—still
one of our own favorites—we might remind ourselves that this is what we might
expect of a nineteen year old, who, through her elopement, her travels and
distance from her father, her attempt to start her own family, but most
pointedly for the sheer fact of her growing up, is constantly experiencing
within herself a disapproving voice as she insecurely and uncertainly
perseveres on.
There
is something of this ambition in our early description of Frankenstein.
Walton tells us first of a broken Frankenstein: “I have found a man who,
before his spirit had been broken by misery, I should have been happy to have
possessed as the brother of my heart” (26). Shortly thereafter we learn
being broken does not exempt Frankenstein from remaining someone of whom it can
still be said: “no one can feel
more deeply than he does the beauties of nature” (28). Walton asks—and I
will later consider if it is in fact what constitutes his very
“brokenness”—“what quality it is which he possesses, that elevates him so
immeasurably above any other person” (28). Then we have a sign (if we
haven’t already a couple of them, in knowing him to be so feeling and so
elevated), not only that he still has spirit but that he has not learned, not
internalized, the lessons he hopes to impart to Walton. Frankenstein
tells Walton to:
[p]repare
to hear of occurrences which are usually deemed marvellous. Were were
among the tamer scenes of nature, I might fear to encounter your unbelief,
perhaps your ridicule; but many things will appear possible in these wild and
mysterious regions, which would provoke the laughter of those unacquainted with
the ever-various powers of nature; —nor can I doubt but that my tale conveys in
its series internal evidence of the truth of the events of which it is
composed. (28)
And here
he stops us short, if more out of befuddlement than wonder, for in the very
effort of making his tale credible to Walton, Frankenstein shows good reason to
doubt the very wisdom he hopes to impart! Note that Frankenstein tells us
the experience of the “ever-varied powers of nature” is empowering,
enfranchising: he yet still knows
what is and what is not possible “in these wild and mysterious regions”
(29). More importantly, note that Frankenstein, knowing the magnitude of
the tale he has to impart, shows
signs of struggling with self-doubt, self-castigation, his fears of being
ridiculed. Most importantly, we note the similarity of this passage to
the one in which he articulates the hubris of thought and demonstrates the sort
of self-belief he tells us got him into such dire straights in the first place.
When
Frankenstein discovers how to create life, he says:
I was
surprised, that among so many men of genius who had directed their enquiries
towards the same science, that I alone should be reserved to discover so
astonishing a secret [. . .]. Remember, I am not recording the vision of a
madman. The sun does not more certainly shine in the heavens, than that
which I now affirm is true. Some miracle might have produced it, yet the
stages of the discovery were distinct and probable. (51)
In both
cases he is offering an account of something important and true but also so
hard to believe it strongly credits the person who appreciates it, placing him
enviably beyond the rest of man, in fact, and yet still insists on its truth,
telling us in both cases that he can
prove it!
There
is another way that by the very means in which he introduces his tale to
Walton, Frankenstein offers reasons for doubting, not his sincerity, but the
degree to which Shelley, through Frankenstein, is using her work to lay out her
own already settled value system.
Notice the modesty and respect for critical judgment Frankenstein shows
Walton upon surmising that he seeks “for knowledge and wisdom, as [he] [. . .]
once did” (28): “I do not know that the relation of my disasters will be
useful to you; yet, when I reflect that you are pursuing the same course,
exposing yourself to the same dangers which have rendered me what I am, I
imagine that you may deduce an apt moral from my tale” (29). Notice, too,
his concern that Walton deduce his own moral from the tale. It seems
clear that Shelley is attempting to make Frankenstein credible through his very
respect for the reasoning powers of man. Yet note the change in Frankenstein
when he:
see[s]
by [Walton’s] [. . .] eagerness and the wonder and hope which your eyes
express, my friend, that you expect to be informed of the secret with which I
am acquainted; that cannot be: listen patiently until the end of my story, and you will easily perceive why I am
reserved upon that subject. I will not lead you on, unguarded and ardent
as I then was, to your destruction and infallible misery. Learn from me,
if not by my precepts, at least by my example, how dangerous is the
acquirement of knowledge and how much happier that man is who believes his
native town to be the world, than he who aspires to become greater than his
nature will allow. (52)
Frankenstein
is now moralizing to Walton, telling him the
lesson he must take from the tale.
I will later discuss why I think for Shelley the very consideration of young
Walton’s “eagerness of wonder and hope” (52) would summon this crushing
declaration by Frankenstein (purportedly for Walton’s own good), but for now I
will highlight signs of uncertainty in Frankenstein at the very moment he
elucidates the moral lesson many critics take to be the obvious moral of the
text proper, to be, rather, the whole
point of the book.
This
lesson, incidentally and importantly, is not what many critics take it to
be: despite its appearance, it is
as much a spurring on for further self-examination and self-exploration as it
is a stop-sign in way of it. Frankenstein does not refer to the dangers
of man’s pride; instead, he refers to
the dangers for those who seek to rise above what their own particular nature allows. This
begs the question: “What, then, is
my particular nature—how do I
rank?” How do we think Shelley, daughter “of Godwin and Mary,” thinks she
compares with other people? Perhaps we see some indication of it in
Walton’s description of Frankenstein, whom he places beyond all other
men. Certainly Frankenstein, when he discusses “our weak and faulty
natures” (28), generalizes about a human condition. But again, this pronouncement is based on what he has
learned through extraordinary life experiences; and this pronouncement, as with
all those he makes, owing to his insistence in his ability to prove it,
evidences an effectual will that clashes with claims of its ineffectuality. It is difficult for me to believe that
Shelley could present us such an extraordinary figure and really think that
Frankenstein was deficient, limited. I believe that Shelley, through
Frankenstein, is offering us a real sense that this—namely, a desire to be great,
coupled with a fear of the consequences of deeming himself so singularly
superior—is a source of considerable inner conflict for her. Frankenstein
will at times devalue his own worth, but as I have shown there are also times
where in bringing the possibility that he is ordinary to the fore, he struggles
in making himself seem wholly credible, in convincing us he truly believes what
he is arguing.
In
the very introduction of the tale Shelley shows signs she is exploring the
possibility that moralizing is a consequence of self-surrender—of
failure. Note that Frankenstein tells Walton that his own tale “may
direct you if you succeed in your undertaking, and console you in case of failure” (29; emphasis added). Reading
this, surely we should ask ourselves whether at some level Shelley is aware
that the very act of writing a moral lesson concerning the dooming consequences
of selfish pride is exactly the kind
of thing one might do to console yourself if you sensed you’d been
compromised. I expect this is why
Shelley introduces Frankenstein by attending to his greatness, even though it
calls her text’s overt moral lesson into question. Shelley is fighting;
she is resisting inviting upon herself the self-assessment as a failure she
knows would follow from telling a wholly convincing moral tale. This is
why she at times resists generalizing about man’s nature, having Frankenstein
say, “Yet why do I say this? I have myself been blasted in these hopes,
yet another may succeed” (210). At nineteen, and with a childhood and
adolescence of a kind I will explore later, she might be asking herself if she
might be this “another,” this someone else, this exception. Nevertheless,
she seems uncertain of life’s outcome, and thus consoles herself throughout
much of the text—with note, what amounts to a kind of Puritanical pride—with
the idea that “the man who imagines his native town to be the world” (52) is
greater than those not similarly
enlightened.
Shelley,
through Frankenstein, is exploring the self-satisfaction, the self-pride that
follows from being a member of a remarkable family—what she has most closely in
mind, I think, when she writes of belonging to a “native town.” Chapter
one begins with a statement by Frankenstein of the superior nature of his own
parents. He tells us that:
[m]y
mother’s tender caresses and my father’s smile of benevolent pleasure while
regarding me, are my first recollections. I was their plaything and their
idol, and something better—their child, the innocent and helpless creature bestowed
on them by Heaven, whom to bring up to good, and whose future lot it was in
their hands to direct to happiness or misery, according as they fulfilled their
duties towards me. With this deep consciousness of what they owed
towards the being to which they had given life, added to the active spirit of
tenderness that animated both, it may be imagined that while during every hour
of my infant life I received a lesson of patience, of charity, and of
self-control, I was so guided by a silken cord that all seemed but one train of
enjoyment to me. (33)
Frankenstein
is likewise conscious of “how peculiarly fortunate [his] [. . .] lot was”
(37), and notes that this gratitude—arising from a comparison with those less
fortunate as them—“assisted the
development of filial love” (37; emphasis added). Frankenstein provides
an example of this downward comparison when he describes Clerval’s parents for
us: “His father was a narrow-minded
trader, and saw idleness and ruin in the aspiration and ambition of his son.
Henry [Clerval] deeply felt the misfortune
of being debarred from a liberal education. He said little; but when
he spoke, I read in his kindling eye and in his animated glance a restrained
but firm resolve, not to be chained to the miserable details of commerce.” (44)
We
find another example at Justine’s trial, where Justine, Frankenstein’s father,
and especially Elizabeth distinguish themselves as apart from the rest
of the town. Frankenstein’s poor regard for his fellow townsmen is
abundantly clear: “My passionate and indignant appeals were lost upon
them. And when I received their cold answers and heard the harsh,
unfeeling reasoning of these men, my purposed avowal died away on my lips”
(86). It is important that we note that what is especially repugnant
about these men is their harshness and lack of feeling, because here too is
evidence that Shelley, through Frankenstein, may be confronting feelings of
anger, feelings of betrayal, she at some level feels towards her own family.
Justine
is not betrayed by her family, but she does suffer self-betrayal for confessing to a crime she did not commit.
She explains she was besieged by a “confessor” who “threatened and menaced [. .
.] until I almost began to think that I was the monster that he said I was”
(84). But after confessing she experiences overwhelming feelings of
shame, telling us “[i]n an evil hour I subscribed to a lie; and now only am I
truly miserable” (84). Elizabeth tries to console her, to give her
strength, saying she “will prove [her] [. . .] innocence” (84), but Justine
shakes “her head mournfully” (84) and says:
‘I do
not fear to die,’ [. . .] that pang is past. God raises my weakness and
gives me courage to endure the worst. I leave a sad and bitter world; and
if you remember me and think of me as of one unjustly condemned, I am resigned
to the fate awaiting me. Learn from me, dear lady, to submit in patience
to the will of heaven!’ (84)
This
surely reminds the reader of Frankenstein’s reply to Walton, when Walton felt
“the greatest eagerness [. . .] to ameliorate his [i.e., Frankenstein’s] fate”
(29):
‘I thank
you,’ he replied, ’for your sympathy, but it is useless; my fate is nearly
fulfilled. I wait but for one event, and then I shall repose in
peace. I understand your feeling,’ continued he, perceiving that I wished
to interrupt him: ‘but you are mistaken, my friend, if thus you will
allow me to name you; nothing can alter my destiny; listen to my history, and
you will perceive how irrevocably it is determined. (29)
Justine,
like Frankenstein, is singled out and faces condemnation, not only from “the
public” but from those friends she most values. She asks them: “And
do you also believe that I am so very, very wicked? Do you also join with
my enemies to crush me, to condemn me?” (83). Frankenstein, too, fears
his new friend’s judgment, speculating that Clerval might ridicule his own tale
if they were in “the tamer scenes of nature” (29). But in Justine’s case,
she is innocent—she is no monster, she is only made to feel as if she is. But if the unfairness of her
self-conviction is meant to distinguish her from the truly guilty, the truly
fallen and monstrous Frankenstein, then why present such strong parallels between
these two scenes so that each seems a duplicate of the other, with one
featuring a false confession and the other, a true one? Is it means to emphasize Frankenstein’s
guilt? Or is it, rather, means for
Shelley to explore her own? That is: Is she offering herself a variety of versions of a similar
experience with judgments of culpability to help her decide whether she
deserves to feel guilty, whether virtue lies through accepting or rejecting the
guilt, and through which choice—to aim to be good, or accept being bad—will
follow the truest freedom?
My
own opinion is that Shelley, through a variety of characters and in a variety
of scenes throughout the text, is meditating on the difficulties involved in
maintaining her own convictions before intimidation from elders—or rather, from
a specific elder: her father. Acquiescence means disappointment, owing to inconstancy to
oneself. We note that Justine’s family is surprised and disappointed that
she, unlike courageous Elizabeth, who braves those who’d hem her in, kowtows to
public authority. But Shelley surely would not do so: one senses throughout Frankenstein such pride in her family we
would expect it to bully through prescriptions from public norms. But
Frankenstein and Justine—and thus surely Shelley as well—are vulnerable to the opinion of her closest friends and
family. And it is when she
experiences conflict between her own desires, her own needs, her own beliefs
and those of her family’s that Shelley encounters a blasting force that brings
to mind considerations of what it might be like to live by the standards of
others, to accept their voice, their judgments, as her own. A sad what if? she ends up exploring
through her vehicles, Frankenstein and Justine.
Justine
experiences a moment when she “subscribed to a lie” that lead immediately to
misery and self-condemnation.
Justine, we note, who was twelve years old when Frankenstein’s family
took her in, is entering adolescence, is growing up, when her transformation
from one with promise to one newly doomed occurs. The precise age of her
crippling is noteworthy because it amounts to, if not further evidence, at
least further impetus to consider as
evidence that the actual moment which dooms and haunts Frankenstein is not when
he awakens the monster, but rather one much earlier in his life, occurring when
he too was entering that stage where he began to see before him “the moment
when [he] [. . .] should put them [i.e., benevolent intentions] in practice and
make [. . .] [himself] useful to [. . .] [his] fellow beings” (87). He
reflects on this moment when—and once again it is important again to pay
attention to the wording:
all
[became] blasted: instead of that serenity of conscience which allowed me
to look back upon the past with self-satisfaction, and from thence to gather
promise of new hopes, I was seized by remorse and the sense of guilt, which
hurried me away to a hell of intense tortures, such as no language can
describe. (87)
Frankenstein’s
monster experiences a similarly painful transformation after working his way to
his climactic meeting with his “friends,” in particular, the fatherly De
Lacey. “Finding [himself] [. . .] unsympathised with, [he] wished to tear
up the trees, spread havoc and destruction around [him]” (132). And it
seems clear that this is the moment which haunts Frankenstein, and which haunts
Shelley herself, a key moment in her life when her hopes were dashed by the
lack of sympathy, by the disregard, of fathers.
Frankenstein
tells us that when he was thirteen years old, after reading through a volume of
books “[a] new light seemed to dawn upon [his] [. . .] mind, and, bounding with
joy, [he] [. . .] communicated [his] [. . .] discovery to [his] [. . .] father”
(38). Frankenstein notes that “[his] father looked carelessly at the
titlepage of [his] [i.e., Frankenstein’s] [. . .] book and said, ‘Ah! Cornelius
Agrippa! My dear Victor, do not waste your time upon this; it is sad
trash’” (38). Frankenstein tells us that this moment was crucial only because, owing to his father’s
carelessness, he continued to explore studies that would count against him in
life. We should not believe him in this, for this is in fact a
remembrance for Shelley’s consideration of the crucial moment of Frankenstein’s
life, and it is a moment which is a certain simulacrum for an experience
Shelley had with her own father at the same age (twelve to thirteen).
There are several reasons why I believe this is the case. The text
itself, independent of any biographical knowledge of Shelley’s life, certainly
points in this direction, but in addition there are scholars that have explored
Shelley’s life, have examined Shelley’s letters, as well as her father’s
letters to her, and believe there was a dramatic change in how Shelley’s father
treated her around this age. And when one keeps Shelley in mind, what was
going on, that had gone on in her
life while reading Frankenstein, we
cannot miss the similarities between her upbringing and Frankenstein’s (and
Frankenstein’s monster’s as well) own. And finally, though Shelley is
near keen to it without of course any recourse to its like, psychoanalytic
explorations of the schism that develops between parents and children when
their needs and desires begin to match especially poorly—i.e., during
adolescence—show how children almost always end up blaming themselves for the
rejection they suffer for pursuing their life goals. Hoping not to tax my
reader’s patience too much, I will explore each piece of evidence in turn in
hopes of offering as powerful, as convincing a case possible, that Shelley’s
trial of Frankenstein is best understood as a trial of her own self for daring
to resist and resent her father’s judgments of her.
Throughout
the text moments of pleasure are raised and subsequently crushed. It is
Walton’s (child-like) look of “wonder” and “hope” and his eagerness “to
be informed of the secret with which [Frankenstein] [. . .] is
acquainted” (51), that has Frankenstein not only refuse to comply but to
commence his lecturing of him. No surprise, this, since Frankenstein once
had his own eager hopes similarly crushed, and so is familiar with the
psychological allowances allotted the defeated. This moment for Frankenstein was the crucial moment life moment for him, the moment where he told
himself, “I am a blasted tree; the bolt has entered my soul” (155), and proof
lies in the nature of the passages where the key word “blasted” appears in the
text and in its absence in the passages involving the creation of the
monster—that is, at the moment most critics believe where all pleasure actually
turned to pain for Frankenstein.
Frankenstein
describes this moment as one where “all was blasted” (87). Critics who
believe the moment he is obsessing over, his creation of life, attend to how
the creature is brought to life by a spark of electricity: they believe this is the scene
foreshadowed earlier with the image of an oak tree being “utterly destroyed” by
a bolt of lightning. But a lightning bolt that leaves nothing behind but
a “blasted stump” (40) matches poorly
with an awakening by a mere spark of electricity. But it is, however, a
perfect match for the passage where
Frankenstein decides he “should put [benevolent intentions] [. . .] into
practice,” a decision which follows with him subsequently concluding that “all
is blasted” (87). The moment where the lightning bolt blasted the oak was
not written to foreshadow Frankenstein’s fateful decision to create life; it
was, instead, a description of what if felt like at the very moment of bringing
in the form of a book his own ambitions, his own determined manner of making a
distinctive, useful contribution to the world to his father for consideration,
for approval, and having him attend to it with but a cursory glance before
dismissing it entirely.
Though
two years pass between his writing of his father’s dismissal and of how all is
blasted, textually, the blasting of the oak follows immediately from Frankenstein’s description of his father’s
reaction to his studies. Following
learning of his father’s disapproval, we hear of Frankenstein encountering a
“man of great research in natural philosophy” (40) who ostensibly inspires a
complete “overthrow[ing] [. . .] of [the lords of his (i.e., Frankenstein’s)
imagination which] [. . .] disinclined [him] [. . .] to pursue [his] [. . .]
accustomed studies. It seemed to [him] as if nothing would or could ever
be known. All that had so long engaged [his] [. . .] attention suddenly
grew despicable” (40). He tells us he dismisses every one of the
sciences, deciding only mathematics, “being [the only branch of study] built
upon secure foundations” (41), worth studying. To inform us of an
encounter which lead him to abandon all his studies, all the lords of the
imagination of his childhood, only a few passages after telling us that the reason
he relates to us the moment of his father’s dismissal is because it encouraged
him to keep at reading, is very
odd. He explains the marked change in course, from eager interest in
studies to sudden disavowal of most of them, as result of a last-ditch attempt
by a “spirit of preservation” to save him. But considering that the voice throughout the book that
keeps appealing to Frankenstein’s better nature, telling him “not [to] [. . .]
brood [on] [. . .] thoughts of vengeance [. . .] but with feelings of peace and
gentleness, that will heal [. . .] the wounds of our minds” (70), that
attempts to dissipate the “gloom which appears to have taken so strong a hold
of [. . .] [his] mind” (142), which warns him of the effects of whatever
current behavior/inclination—it festers current wounds (70), it “prevents
improvement or enjoyment” (88)—this mysterious spirit of preservation, no
doubt, is but the already abundantly familiar voice of his father.
No, Frankenstein does not continue his childhood studies because his father
failed to have a notable impact upon
him; rather, the impact of his cursory glance could not have had a more
reverberating, long-lasting effect on him. Frankenstein persists not in spite of his father, but instead to spite him, for his “harsh, unfeeling”
(86) reaction to his developing interests and hopes for the future.
I
believe the reason a fatherly scientist appears in the text soon after the
devastating blow to his own (i.e., Frankenstein’s) explorations and
self-confidence, is that Shelley, imagining a similar confrontation with her
own father, must soon engage with the feelings that arose from this near recall
of her own experience. I argue mostly through an appeal to common sense,
but Shelley is clearly aware of the
pain involved in repressing feelings:
“Even in my own heart I could give no expression to my sensations—they
weighed on me with a mountain’s weight, and their excess destroyed my agony
beneath them” (144). Frankenstein is enraged by his father’s
inattention. It brings to mind one
of the few instances where Frankenstein considers the possibility that his
father is not perfect, is not right.
And it is followed by the introduction into his tale of M. Krempe and M.
Waldman, who offer Frankenstein all his father failed to offer him.
M.
Krempe and M. Waldman are not to be imagined devils-in-the-guise-of-angels who
lead Frankenstein on into sin. It is important that Shelley establishes
that they both share with Frankenstein’s father a preference for thinkers other
than Frankenstein’s previous lords of his imagination. What Frankenstein
had hoped from his father, supposedly, was merely for him to “take the pains to
explain to [him] [. . .] that the principles of Agrippa had been entirely
exploded” (38). M. Krempe shares Frankenstein’s father’s belief that his
(i.e., Frankenstein’s) studies have been a waste, but substantiates Frankenstein’s feeling that his father was still
somehow in error. In fact, he
makes it a crime:
‘Every
minute,’ continued M. Krempe with warmth, ‘every instant that you have wasted
on those books is utterly and entirely lost. You have burdened your
memory with exploded systems and useless names. Good God! In what desert
land have you lived, where no on was kind enough to inform you that these
fancies which you have so greedily imbibed are a thousand years old and as
musty as they are ancient? I little expected, in this enlightened and
scientific age, to find a disciple of Albertus Magnus and Paracelsus. My
dear sir, you must begin your studies entirely anew.’ (45)
We hear
here not only an accusation that his father must have been neglectful, but that
the native land he came from must have been a desert island. Note, too,
that M. Krempe speaks here in a warm
voice, a marked contrast to Frankenstein’s father’s cold dismissal.
M.
Waldman does M. Krempe one better in that “[h]e heard with attention the little
narration concerning my studies, and smiled at the names of Cornelius Agrippa
and Paracelsus, but without the contempt that M. Krempe had exhibited”
(47). He substantiates the feeling Frankenstein once had as a child that
these old philosophers had something significant to offer him: “He said
that ‘these were men to whose indefatigable zeal modern philosophers were
indebted for most of the foundations of their knowledge’” (47). He comes
across as an ideal father-figure, one who gives lie to Frankenstein’s claim
that all he wanted from his father was to show that “the powers of the [these
early philosophers] [. . .] were chimerical” (38). Not so: the thirteen-year-old Frankenstein who
came to his father with “[a] new light [. . .] dawn[ing] on his mind [. . .]
[,] bounding with joy [ . . .] [,] [and who] communicated [his] [. . .]
discovery to [his] [. . .] father” (38), was hoping for what every child
wants—validation and enthusiasm for his/her own life pursuits. M. Waldman
appears in the text because at some level Shelley is aware that she was
mistreated, was aware she deserved better, and it is no coincidence that in M.
Waldman, who is “[h]appy [. . .] to have gained a disciple” (48), Frankenstein
has “found a true friend” (49)—or rather, an ideal father-figure; one who
doesn’t just happen to show up his own.
It
is no accident that Waldman is described as smiling at Frankenstein:
Frankenstein’s own father, with a “smile of benevolent pleasure while
regarding” him, was Frankenstein’s first recollection of him. But around
adolescence Shelley stopped receiving those smiles, and desperately in further
need of them, creates for herself M. Waldman. And from Frankenstein’s
subsequent description of him, we know we here have a man compared to whom even
his own father suffers from a steep downward comparison:
His
gentleness was never tinged by dogmatism, and his instructions were given with
an air of frankness and good nature, that banished every idea of
pedantry. In a thousand ways he smoothed for me the path of knowledge,
and made the most abstruse enquiries clear and facile to my apprehension.
(49)
Buoyed
by the love from this good man, Frankenstein will begin to engage in the
laboratory experiments that will have him discover the purportedly chimerical
ability to create life. Some critics attend to M. Waldman’s declaration
that science “penetrate[s] into the recesses of nature, and show how she works
in her hiding-places” (49), and argue it as proof that Shelley herself
disapproves of him. But if such a man as M. Waldman is in for a hard time
from critics, I am fearful to know whom they would praise, for he is a near
ideal father, only one, though we might imagine him, pretend at having him,
most of us still have trouble convincing ourselves we actually deserve.
Shelley,
in imagining this perfect father, one far superior to her own, surely felt
considerable guilt (sacrilege!), and this explains why she has Frankenstein
accuse himself of neglecting his family, saying:
I knew
my silence disquieted them; and I well remembered the words of my father:
‘I know that while you are pleased with yourself, you will think of us with
affection, and we shall hear regularly from you. You must pardon me if I
regard any interruption in your correspondence as a proof that your other
duties are equally neglected.’ (54)
We note
the discord, the inconsistency, between how his father is made to seem here and
how Frankenstein described his father at the beginning of the text. His
father had been described as someone who was “deeply conscious [. . .] of what
[he] [. . .] owed towards [. . .] the being to which they had given life,” and
who “fulfilled [his] [. . .] duties towards [. . .] him” (33). With his
failure to attend to his son, we have already seen signs of his neglect, and in
this passage we have a father who seems mostly focused on what his son owes
him. Frankenstein does not accuse his father of inconstancy, but it is
one of things his characters notice as a significant fault in others. The
monster says to Frankenstein, for example: “How inconstant are your feelings! [B]ut a moment ago
you were moved by my representations and why do you again harden yourself to my
complaints?” (142). Elizabeth writes of Justine’s mother that “[t]he poor
woman was very vacillating in her repentance. She sometimes begged
Justine to forgive her unkindness but much oftener accused her of having caused
the deaths of her brothers and sister” (64).
“[W]hen
you are pleased with yourself, you will think of us” (33), is not one of the
more appealing nuggets of life advice I’ve encountered in literature, and it
surely smacks of exactly the kind of moralizing his father ostensibly
disapproved of. I think that Shelley is aware of this, is aware that her
own father did not practice what he preached, and buoyed by her creation of an
ideal father who validates her own needs has Frankenstein doubt his father’s
advice: “I then thought that my father would be unjust if he ascribed my
neglect to vice, or faultiness” (54). But he follows this by informing us
he no longer thinks this way:
but I am
now convinced that he was justified in conceiving that I should not be
altogether free from blame. A human being in perfection ought always to
preserve a calm and peaceful mind, and never to allow passion or a transitory
desire to disturb his tranquility. I do not think that the pursuit of knowledge
is an exception to this rule. If the study to which you apply yourself
has a tendency to weaken your affections, and to destroy your taste for
those simple pleasures in which no alloy can possibly mix, then that study is
certainly unlawful, that is to say, not befitting the human mind.
If this rule were always observed; if no man allowed any pursuit
whatsoever to interfere with the tranquility of his domestic affections, Greece
had not been enslaved; Caesar would have spared his country; America would have
been discovered more gradually; and the empires of Mexico and Peru had not been
destroyed. (54)
He
interrupts himself to offer excuse for what he prefers to see as his
moralizing, but which owing to its striking length is best understood as
evidence of the profound ripple effect, the profound resulting affect—shock—writing Frankenstein’s fathers’
words has upon Shelley immediately after writing them. Shelley, through
Frankenstein, is attempting to process, make surer sense of the moralizing,
commanding tone of Frankenstein’s father—a simulacra of her own—whose immediate
effect is but to disturb her so profoundly it shocks her into assuming an
ostensibly wiser and clearly older philosophic address. Such sober
“dressings” protect her some from accusation, buy her time to process all that
just went on in her fictional re-encounter with her own father, something that
requires a significant pause because at some level Shelley is aware that a
father who writes of a child’s duties is not likely simply being attendant to
the child’s best interest but rather
more his own. This is why we
encounter here talk in praise of simple, of moderated (read: compromised)
pleasures: the pressure to
acquiesce, to accept being owned by others’ demands and to make it seem for the
best, is crushing.
But
how much respect is due such a father, really? Shelley, through
Frankenstein, has already criticized Clerval’s father for attempting to
determine his career path.
Moreover, we read that Clerval was not a fool to the true nature of his
father’s intent; instead, he “deeply felt
his [i.e., Clerval’s] misfortune” (44). Fortunately, Clerval
possessed a “firm resolve, not to be chained” (44). So Shelley, again through Frankenstein, is not only
cognizant of fathers’ inclination to dominate their children, she shows she
thinks the child who resists the one worthy of salute. Clerval’s father saw “idleness and ruin
in the aspirations and ambition of his son,” and this too was worthy of a harsh
judgment from Frankenstein: “his father was a narrow-minded trader” (44). Shelley, now imagining for herself a
father—Frankenstein’s—who, unlike Clerval’s trader, comes closer to being a
reproduction of her own, is not simply trying to rationalize Frankenstein’s
father’s words. She is also testing them, to see if she can permit
herself to judge her father in the same way Frankenstein judges Clerval for
perpetration of the same crime.
If
Shelley let Frankenstein be fully aware of just how wrong his father was to
“ascrib[e] [Frankenstein’s] [. . .] neglect to vice, or faultiness” (54), she
would likely understand this as weighing toward a harsh critique of her own
father as well. She would
understand that the reason Clerval is
behaving heroically while resisting his father, is because this isn’t the
easiest of things to do, especially in previous eras where do-as-you’re-told!
not what-color-is-your-parachute? principally moved the adolescent-parent
dynamic. Making such a judgment
alienates you from your family; you are not like them, making hopes of claiming
your father’s love something to be abandoned, once and for all. But if,
after praising Clerval for his determination, she has Frankenstein surrender to
his father’s judgment, this would amount to self-surrender, capitulation for
Shelley, one near obvious to her, which would make every attempt to make it
seem all for the best, equally obvious rationalizing. The anxieties
arising from her two conflicting desires—to never betray herself, but also to
prove her father always in the right—lead to the re-doubling of her effort to
wipe out all doubts Frankenstein has towards his father. Thus we
read: “My father made no reproach in his letters, and only took notice of
my silence by enquiring into my occupations more particularly than before”
(54).
When
Clerval enters the tale, again we hear Frankenstein maintain that freedom lies
in terminating his [i.e., Frankenstein’s] explorations: “I hope, I
sincerely hope, that all these employments are now at an end, and that I am at
length free” (59). But what does such “freedom” open up for
Frankenstein? The god-awful, it
would seem. When Frankenstein
returns home, Shelley has Elizabeth “express a sorrowful delight to see me”
(75). He had returned late: “Ah! I wish you had come three months
ago, and then you would have found us all joyous and delighted” (75). For
the hubris of ignoring his family, for not thinking of his family when he
experienced pleasure, for disobeying his father!, Shelley imagines for him a situation
(the death of his brother) that could only substantiate his sense of guilt, his
inclination toward self-reproof.
But experiencing guilt—a confession to knowing yourself in the
wrong—offers no respite, no rescue, for his father chastises his son for his
brooding (though Frankenstein describes it as an attempt “to inspire [him] [. .
.] with fortitude, and awaken in [him] [. . .] the courage to dispel the dark
cloud which brooded over [. . .] [him]” [87]):
‘Do you
think, Victor,’ said he, ‘that I do not suffer also? No one could love a
child more than I loved your brother’—tears came into his eyes as he spoke—‘but
is it not a duty to the survivors that we should refrain from augmenting their
unhappiness by an appearance of immoderate grief? It is also a duty owed
to yourself; for excessive sorrow prevents improvement or enjoyment, or even
the discharge of daily usefulness, without which no man is fit for society.’
(88)
Yet
saintly, “heroic[,] and suffering” (88) Elizabeth was “sad and desponding; she
no longer took delight in her ordinary occupations; all pleasure seemed to her
sacrilege toward the dead” (89). Frankenstein will have a tough time
finding a way out, for if happy, he is being disrespectful to the newly dead,
and if he grieves, he shows immoderacy. He is in fact brought tight-walk
close to the kind of double-bind situation where no solution would end up
proving available to him, that the psychiatrist R.D. Laing believes is related
to the development of schizophrenic symptoms. I suspect this is why
Shelley introduces into the tale the consideration that “[t]here was always
scope for fear, so long as anything I loved remained behind” (89): Shelley, presenting herself with a
facsimile of her own self-conflicted state, is imagining for her own
consideration the respite to be found in the most terrible of available
solutions—namely, leaving loved ones permanently
behind by becoming unknown and unlovable.
I
mentioned that there are several reasons why I suspect Shelley had once
experienced a terrifying moment of parental abandonment that thereafter weighed
heavily upon her. I have discussed evidence in the text that
Frankenstein, though having difficulty admitting it to himself, was crushed by
a sudden change in his father’s reaction to him around the age of thirteen—that
is, at the age where he most sought approval for his own chosen life
course—which inspired a subsequent effort to individuate anyway, to imagine
something better for himself, better father, better surroundings, as well as
the very creation of life from knowledge of the kind his father had previously
dismissed as simply a waste of time.
But followed by collapsing into self-hatred, by rejoining a family that
put him down, and by initiating a desperate, swirling search for just what it
would take for him to be free from the dictates of others. But before exploring where these
desperate imaginings took him, an exploration which follows one of a “serene”
moment protected from a “disastrous” future that compares rather well with
Keats’ own explorations of the same in “Ode to a Grecian Urn,” I would like to
offer biographical proof that Frankenstein
is itself such a frozen moment for Shelley, one she is using to help sort out
just what the hell happened? in adolescence after having known a much less
debilitating, and perhaps even mostly pleasing, childhood.
Concerning
Shelley’s difficulties with her father upon emerging into adulthood,
Hill-Miller writes:
Mary
Godwin passed through childhood, she satisfied her passionate attachment to
William Godwin by living up to his literary expectations, by identifying
herself with his hopes for her, and by modeling herself after him [. . .] [,]
as [she] [. . .] entered adolescence, William Godwin’s aloof demeanor seemed to
turn to outright rejection. In fact, the beginning of Mary’s adolescence
marked a long period of alienation from her father, an alienation that only
ended when she married Percy Bysshe Shelley at age nineteen. This
parental rejection is central to Mary Shelley and her career: it haunted her
all of her life and became emblematic of the many other types of rejection she
encountered. It shaped her response to her burgeoning femininity and gave
birth to her vision of the precarious nature of daughter-hood; it provided part
of the creative impulse for her first two novels—Frankenstein and Mathilda—both
of which tell the story of the daughter’s painful induction into adult
womanhood. (31)
She
believes that “[a]s Mary Godwin grew older and entered adolescence, her need
for emotional support from her father increased” (31). She refers to the
work of Nancy Chodorow and “the psychic currents of the oedipal nuclear family”
(31) to explain Shelley’s rejection by her father, telling us that “[f]rom a
father’s point of view [. . .] the daughter’s passage through adolescence often
creates an anxious—and even threatening—moment. As the daughter passes
out of the sexual latency of childhood and begins to develop into a mature
woman, the father often rejects her. As Lynda Boose explains, the
daughter’s new physical maturity invites incestuous desire” (31-32).
I
admit I look to other theorists for the whys behind paternal rejection (by
which I mean, I don’t think it owes mostly to incestuous desires), but I find
what Hill-Miller has to say about the rejection—that it “meant the end of a
childhood full of wide horizons and possibility” (32)—along with her
documentation of the sort of distancing from her father Shelley experienced
during her adolescence, important to note:
In the
spring of 1811, when she [Shelley] was thirteen and a half years old, she was
sent away [. . .] in the hope that the sea air would cure her. [. .
.] Though Godwin had good medical reason to send Mary away, and though the
separation was intended to calm Mary’s feelings as well as preserve the peace
of the whole household, Mary could not help but read the separation from her
father as an abandonment—and an abandonment directly connected to the fact that
she was becoming a woman. [. . .] Godwin wrote to his daughter only four times,
and failed to visit her for her fourteenth birthday, though he was vacationing
in the area. (34)
Shelley
experiences distance from her father
as his rejection of her. She is
sent away because she is “bad, ” because she is growing up, and therefore apart
from him. Little wonder, perhaps, that Frankenstein gets up to no good
while away at university, for it proves her father was right about her, would
work to demonstrate her the repentant who had come to accept the full wisdom of
his ways. And little wonder, perhaps, that when Frankenstein leaves for
university it is described as something beyond his control: “it [i.e., earlier desires to take his
place amongst men] would have been folly to repent” (44), though he was
“unwilling to quit the sight of those that remained” (43).
When
Shelley returns home “family conflict resumed with a vengeance” (Hill-Miller
34), and she is sent away once again, this time to Scotland.
Hill-Miller’s discussion of the implications of this event for Shelley’s life,
need also be considered:
Mary
Godwin’s stay in Scotland became the event that marked and engulfed her
adolescence. When she wore a new introduction for the 1831 edition of Frankenstein, Mary Shelley reflected
that she had “lived principally in the country as a girl, and passed a
considerable time in Scotland” (Frankenstein
223). This description of her early years must have come as a surprise to
her father, because Mary principally lived in Godwin’s home during her
childhood, and she spent time in the country and Scotland only when Godwin sent
her there to restore her health and the family peace. The point is that
Mary’s absences from Godwin’s house—absences she read as acts of banishment and
paternal rejection—-became the events that defined her adolescence,
overshadowing all else. (35)
Shelley
never forgot her early childhood, but her obsession to make right, to make
sense of her own adolescence, so occupied her subsequent attention the constant
sorting and re-sorting of memories associated with her adolescence in a search
for answers made them the memories most available for recall.
When
the sixteen-year-old Mary eloped with Percy Shelley to the Continent, Godwin
was horrified; “[h]e felt robbed of his favorite daughter, cheated of his
literary heir, and deprived of the material link to his cherished past with
Mary Wollstonecraft” (Hill-Miller 38):
There
followed a long period of even more intense estrangement between Godwin and his
daughter, an estrangement that formed the specific background against which
Mary Shelley conceived and began Frankenstein. As Godwin commented in
August 1814, before Mary, Percy, and Jane returned from the Continent,
‘Jane has been guilty of indiscretion only [. . .] [,] Mary has been guilty of a crime.’ [. . .] Godwin cut
himself off from his daughter completely. He refused to communicate with
Mary at all and forbade Fanny Imlay to see or talk to her half-sister.
Godwin did not write or speak to Mary when she lost her first child in
February 1815, or when she bore a son, named William in honor of Godwin
himself, on 24 January 1816.” (Hill-Miller 39; emphasis added)
Godwin
abandoned Shelley at the moment of the birth of her own son, the same
astonishingly cruel act that Frankenstein inflicts upon his own creation.
This was revenge for Shelley’s crime of self-individuation on the Continent and
for creating a family that would claim attention away from him. I will
mimic Frankenstein and insist to my reader that I am not telling falsehoods
here. In a letter written to
Shelley after her writing Frankenstein,
and after the death of another child, Godwin belittles Shelley’s mourning and
tells her in a truly terrifying passage very reminiscent of the passage in Frankenstein where his father instructs
Frankenstein to moderate his grief, to “[r]emember, too, that though at first
your nearest connections may pity you in this state, yet that, when they see
you fixed in selfishness and ill-humour, and regardless of the happiness of
everyone else, they will finally cease to love you, and scarcely learn to
endure you” (Hill-Miller 48).
She
gives us good reason to suspect that Frankenstein does not really represent Percy Shelley, as critics such as Hindle
insist is the case, but rather Mary
Shelley. Hill-Miller reminds us that Mary was raised by her father to be
his son, to be his literary heir:
In the
years leading up to her adolescence, Mary Godwin emerged as her father’s
potential intellectual heir, the child most suited to carry on his work as a
writer and thinker [. . .]. He
entertained great hopes for her. He proudly described her to a
correspondent as “singularly bold, somewhat imperious, and active of mind.” [.
. .] As Mary Shelley herself put it many years later, speaking of her father’s
expectations for her, “I was nursed and fed with a love of glory. To be
something great and good was the precept given me by my father.” [. . .]
Young Mary Godwin took her father’s hopes entirely to heart; she learned to
measure herself against her parents and to envision herself inheriting their
intellectual legacy. As she wrote a correspondent in 1827, “her greatness
of soul [Mary Wollstonecraft’s] & my father[’s] high talents have
perpetually reminded me that I ought to degenerate as little as I could from
those from whom I derived my being [. . .]. [M]y chief merit must always
be derived, first from the glory these wonderful beings have shed [around] me,
& then for the enthusiasm I have for excellence” (25)
Shelley
had an “education and a childhood that in today’s vocabulary might be described
as non-gendered—that is, an education that made the least possible
differentiation between males and females, that encouraged daughters to develop
professional aspirations, and that allowed daughters to envision themselves in
many roles, including those reserved for sons” (Hill-Miller 30). She was
singled out as singularly great, and evidently still had in mind to evidence
her greatness, to demonstrate it to the literary world, well past her writing
of Frankenstein. Mary aimed to
be victorious—Frankenstein’s pride is surely also her own.
And
of what results from Frankenstein’s pride—is there any evidence in Mary’s life
to shed light on why the monster appears in the novel? Hill-Miller
continues:
[But]
[t]o say that William Godwin gave his oldest natural daughter the aspiration
and training necessary to make her a writer—that is, all the expectations of
literary inheritance and sonship—is not to say that their relationship was
always warm and affectionate. Quite the contrary: Godwin was
emotionally withdrawn and often cold; he knew, and his children saw, that
effusive displays of tender feeling were generally beyond his emotional
grasp. [. . . ] Mary Shelley eventually attributed her father’s emotional
distance to his shyness and to inability to grasp his children’s feelings
quickly. (25)
We find
here the best evidence for understanding Shelley as creating Frankenstein’s
monster to explore her childhood, perhaps to see if her troubles in adolescence
owed to something that went wrong earlier, perhaps something she did, or was, that made her worthy of being
disowned. We recall the monster asking himself, “Was I, then, a monster,
a blot upon the earth, from which all men fled and whom all men disowned?” (Shelley
117).
We
mustn’t be over-hasty, though, to assume the monster as best understood as a single entity, because there is evidence
for understanding the monster as embodying different identities, different
people—sometimes Mary Shelley, sometimes her father—at different times in the
text. Note the passage in which the monster chastises Frankenstein,
telling him to “[b]e calm I intreat you to hear me” (96), and asking him:
[h]ave I
not suffered enough, that you seek to increase my misery? Life, although
it may only be an accumulation of anguish , is dear to me, and I will defend
it. [. . . ] I was benevolent and good; misery made me a find. Make me
happy, and I shall again be virtuous” (96-97).
There
are similarities between this passage, I think, and a passage from a letter
written from Frankenstein’s father to his son:
Come
dearest Victor; you alone can console Elizabeth. She weeps continually
and accuses herself unjustly as the cause of his death; her words pierce my
heart. We are all unhappy, but will not that be an additional motive for
you, my son, to return and be our comforter? (70)
Both the
father and the monster are making appeals to Frankenstein to satisfy them with
a deed only he can accomplish for them. Both explain they are suffering,
and hold their suffering as dwarfing the importance of whatever Frankenstein is
himself experiencing, the significance of his own concerns, and thus the
fatherly appeal to family duties, to common decency, as well as the
fatherly address of “Come Victor” and “be calm I entreat you to hear me,” we
hear from both father and monster. (The same address, we note, often
encountered in Shelley’s father’s letters to her.)
There
is psychological evidence for understanding children who believe they possess
lords of the imagination somehow actually as friends, and that do in a sense in fact possess them (and
are not yet so much possessed by
them), which do function to help them
feel protected, safe, and empowered, as coming to experience them as
castigating monsters upon adolescence. The psychohistorian Lloyd DeMause
informs us that:
[C]hildren
usually feel guilty about being traumatized. “I must have been too noisy,
because mommy left me” was my sincere belief when my mother left my
father. I also believed I deserved my father’s strappings because I
wasn’t obedient enough. This is why children set up a separate, internal self
as a “protector” to try to stop themselves from ever being noisy, pushy,
sexual, demanding, in fact, to stop them from growing and thus re-experiencing
trauma. At first, these internal “protectors” are friendly;
sometimes they are represented as imaginary playmates or even as protective
alters [. . .]. Later,
particularly when adolescence brings on opportunities for greater exploration
and especially dating [important to note in regards to Keats’ “Ode to a Grecian
Urn”], these protective selves become persecutory selves that “have
had it” with the host self and actually try to harm it. Their
persecutory self says, “It’s not happening to me, it’s happening to her,
and she deserves it! (6)
While
Frankenstein’s lords of the imagination encourage hubris, the monster reads and
contemplates powerful voices that try to caution him away from
over-ambition. These include
Volney’s Ruins of Empires, with its moral lessons skimmed from the
collapse of once-great empires, Plutarch’s Lives, which led him “to admire peaceable
lawgivers, Numa, Solon, and Lycurgus in preference to Romulus and Theseus”
(125), and Milton’s Paradise Lost,
which has him reflect that he had “allowed [his] [. . .] thoughts, unchecked by
reason, to ramble in the fields of Paradise, and dared to fancy amiable and
lovely creatures sympathising with my feelings and cheering my gloom”
(127). Many readers end up sympathizing with the monster and seem almost
to hate Frankenstein: Mightn’t
this owe to that while the monster attends to voices which tell of his
fallibility, Frankenstein listens to those which encourage further ambition,
that is, to their also being under orders from old lords of their own, gone
monster?
DeMause
argues that the kind of wounds incurred from intuiting at an early age that your parents may often be
indifferent to or even actually at some level hate you, is ultimately far more severe than what might follow from
their physical beatings. Most
times, these emotional hurts never
heal, and end up rattling on throughout your lifetime, for the most part
determining its course:
Traumas
are defined as injuries to the private self, rather than just painful
experiences, since non-painful injuries to the self [. . .] are more traumatic
to the self than, say, more painful accidents. Without a well-developed,
enduring private self, people feel threatened by all progress, all
freedom, all new challenges, and then experience annihilation anxiety, fears
that the fragile self is disintegrating, since situations that call for
self-assertion trigger memories of [. . .] abandonment. Masterson calls
this by the umbrella term “abandonment depressions,” beneath which he says,
“ride the Six Horsemen of the Psychic Apocalypse: Depression, Panic,
Rage, Guilt, Helplessness (hopelessness), and Emptiness (void) [that] wreak
havoc across the psychic landscape leaving pain and terror in their
wake.” Whether the early traumas or rejections were because the [parents]
[. . .] were openly abandoning, over-controlling and abusive, clinging, or
just threatened by the child’s emerging individuation, the results are much the
same—the child learns to fear parts of his or her potential self that threatens
the disapproval or loss of the [. . .] parent. (7)
I think
we see here why Frankenstein rejects (he does this at least a couple of times)
the very same philosophers his father so disapproves of, and why, after being
subject to constant chiding from his father for their distance, he eventually
leaves university for home.
But
returning home, re-merging with the parent, itself has horrible
consequences. DeMause tells us that, according to Socarides:
fears of
growth, individuation, and self assertion that carry threatening feelings of
disintegration lead to desires to merge with the omnipotent mother, literally
to crawl back into the womb, desires which immediately turn into fears of
maternal engulfment, since the merging would involve total loss of the
self. When Socarides’ patients make moves to individuate—like moving into
their own apartment or getting a new job—they have dreams of being swallowed by
whirlpools of devoured by monsters. The only salvation from these
maternal engulfment wishes/fears is a “flight to external reality from internal
reality.” (7)
The need
to fly away to an external reality, to flee home, away from internal reality,
may be what Frankenstein is doing when he leaves his family to wander through
the valleys, and why this sublime landscape, though it “did not remove [his] [.
. .] grief, [. . .] subdued and tranquillised it” (93). He tells us as
much himself: “Sometimes I could cope with the sullen despair that
over-whelmed me; but sometimes the whirlwind passions of my soul drove me to
seek, by bodily exercise and by change of place, some relief from my
intolerable sensations” (91).
DeMause
does not believe trauma unavoidably leads to certain self-destructive or
self-denying thoughts and behaviors, though. So long as the memories “are
not dissociated, if they can be remembered by the conscious mind, [. . .] are
not split off,” they will not service “blam[ing] [our]selves for [our]
persecution” (7). People who have therapists are probably not really best
understood as society’s most sick, but rather as amongst its least defeated: evident in their very decision to seek
help is their awareness that something has gone wrong (or that something was
never quite right), and they have it in them to address their troubles—at best,
also in ways that could not be more unlikely to keep their more troubling
aspects from being discussed and meaningfully explored. DeMause describes a patient of
Masterson’s who should remind us strongly of Frankenstein, of the feelings he
felt before and after his act of hubris:
I was
walking down the street and suddenly I was engulfed in a feeling of absolute
freedom. I could taste it. I knew I was capable of doing whatever I
wanted. When I looked at other people, I really saw them without being
concerned about how they were looking at me [. . .]. I was just being myself and
thought that I had uncovered the secret of life: being in touch
with your own feelings and expressing them openly with others, not worrying so
much about how others felt about you. Then just as suddenly as it came,
it disappeared. I panicked and started thinking about the million things
I had to do at the studio, of errands I needed to run after work. I began
to feel nauseous and started sweating. I headed for my apartment, running
most of the way. When I got in, I felt that I had been
pursued. By what? Freedom, I guess [or maybe by a monster]. (8)
This
moment of total awareness and complete happiness matches well with
Frankenstein’s own upon discovering the secret of life:
Whence,
I often asked myself, did the principle of life proceed? It was a bold
question, and one which has ever been considered as a mystery; yet with how
many things are we upon the brink of becoming acquainted, if cowardice or
carelessness did not restrain our enquiries. I revolved these circumstances in
my mind, and determined thenceforth to apply myself [.] I became acquainted
with the science of anatomy [.] I do not ever remember to have trembled
[. . .] or to have feared [.] I was led to examine [;] I saw [. .
.] the fine form of man [.] I beheld the corruption of death
[.] I saw how the worm inherited the wonders of the eye and brain.
I paused, examining and analysing all the minutiae of causation, as exemplified
in the change from life to death, and death to life, until from the midst of
this darkness a sudden light broke in upon me—a light so brilliant and
wondrous, yet so simple, that while I became dizzy with the immensity of
the prospect which it illustrated, I was surprised, that among so many men of
genius who had directed their enquiries towards the same science, that I alone
should be reserved to discover so astonishing a secret. [. . .] The
astonishment which I had at first experienced on this discovery soon gave place
to delight and rapture. (55-6)
But
after he beholds “the accomplishment of [his] [. . .] toils,” he experiences
“an anxiety that almost amounted to agony” (56). And this switch from
absolute bliss to absolute panic and misery is similar to that experienced by
Masterson’s patient:
The
different accidents are not so changeable as the feelings of human
nature. I had worked hard for nearly two years, for the sole purpose of
infusing life into an inanimate body. For this I had deprived myself of
rest and health. I had desired it with an ardour that far exceeded
moderation; but now that I had finished, the beauty of the dream vanished, and
breathless horror and disgust filled my heart. Unable to endure the
aspect of the being I had created, I rushed out of the room, and continued a
long time traversing my bedchamber, unable to compose my mind to sleep.
(56)
Pleasure
arising from an accomplishment that distinguishes him as apart from and
superior to other people, leads to a flight to external reality.
Shelley,
through Frankenstein, is to some extent realizing that addressing her
inclination toward self-castigation requires figuring out a way to ignore her
father’s commands, not in accepting them, without this amounting to the kind of
scornful repudiation of him we saw Frankenstein and Clerval suffer upon
Clerval’s father. This solution, I think, is something she is
investigating via her vehicle
Frankenstein, but for herself, because though Frankenstein is eternally damned,
damnation blesses him with a wondrous new power.
Late
in the text, when Frankenstein is recovering from illness, his doctor, Mr.
Kirwin, exclaims “in a rather severe tone”: “I should have thought, young
man, that the presence of your father would have been welcome instead of
inspiring such violent repugnance” (174). Frankenstein will now tell his
father the real reason for his “madness” that previously he’d been unable to
share with anyone. His father listens to him, and “with an expression of
unbounded wonder,” says, “My dearest Victor, what infatuation is this? My
dear son, I entreat you never to make such an assertion again” (180). But Frankenstein does not
acquiesce. Instead, he energetically cries out, “‘I am not mad, [. . .]
the sun and the heavens, who have viewed my operations, can bear witness of my
truth. I am the assassin of those most innocent victims; they died by my
machinations” (180). Shelley tells
us that “[t]he conclusion of this speech convinced [Frankenstein’s] [. . .]
father that [his] [. . .] ideas were deranged, and he [i.e., the father]
instantly changed the subject of our conversation” (180). I think this is
a replay of Frankenstein’s childhood encounter with his father where his
own explorations were belittled as mere nonsense, but this time his father is
not right but overhasty, this time he is just plain wrong. And this time
Frankenstein does not belittle his beliefs as false imaginings because he knows
he is right. It is an encounter between two minds where the father shows
himself possessed of the smaller.
Moreover,
we have a sense that when the father turns to other subjects, his son is no
longer listening to him; a crucial moment has occurred, and Frankenstein is now
freed from his father’s opinions and judgments of him. Shelley has
Frankenstein understand that he knows himself better than his father
does. Perhaps the significance of this moment is such that the deaths of
his family members which soon follow, which now include both Elizabeth and his
father, amount to external evidence that he has found a way free of torments—no
further need to grapple with them required. Shelley needed to figure out a way in which Frankenstein’s
father could still remain good—as it is too painful to imagine her father
otherwise—and where Frankenstein’s own independence makes him bad—thereby
validating Shelley’s father’s judgment of her—but in a way which secretly
proves mostly liberating. Shelley
finds one in the Blakean assessment of goodness as innocence, and badness as
corruption through experience. Shelley no longer has Frankenstein listen
to his reprimands to be happy, his encouragements to abandon his studies, or
his requirement to turn away from happy thoughts towards servicing his
family. He heeds no more of his
father’s advice because his father is in a sense the child; his father cannot
appreciate the truths accessible to Frankenstein from Frankenstein’s far
greater, more ranging, experiencing of the world. Importantly, his father
is still characterized as being well-intentioned, he is still to be
distinguished from Clerval’s tyrant of a father. But he cannot also
be right, because his very goodness precludes this possibility.
Frankenstein, who once speculated that man’s “superior [sensibilities] [. . .]
to those apparent in the brute [. . .] only renders them more necessary
beings” (94), and that “[i]f our impulses were confined to hunger, thirst, and
desire, we might be nearly free” (94), has found a way to claim freedom without
denying his superior intellectual capacities. For Shelley, I think that
this amounts to a refusal to falsely confess the wrongness of her way of thinking.
In
Frankenstein’s last conversation with his father, he is attending to other
voices. There is no exploration of, no engagement with, his father’s
lessons; instead, Frankenstein, mimicking, claiming
the authority of his father, offers but a short cursory comment: “Such
were the lessons of my father” (184). Frankenstein’s mind is on his
creation, on his monster. Because he can no longer be reached, is no
longer to be understood by man, Frankenstein is alone. This to many
critics is the consequence—the punishment—for Frankenstein’s hubris, but it is
in fact a state of exclusion, of being, Shelley was struggling toward—not to be
apart from man, but to be able to tolerate and appreciate the aloneness of
independent thinking. As the psychologist Nathaniel Branden remarks, “We
are social animals [. . .] [;] [w]hile it may sometimes be necessary, we do not
normally enjoy long periods of being alienated from the thinking and beliefs of
those around us, especially those we respect and love. [Thus] [o]ne of the
most important forms of heroism is the heroism of consciousness, the heroism of
thought: the willingness to
tolerate aloneness” (50). We see, through Frankenstein, that Shelley
herself finds independence problematic because her father wants her to turn her
thoughts to her family—to him—when
she takes pleasure from her own activity, her own creations, her own thoughts,
or when she attends to those outside the family circle. In imagining herself, through her
creation Frankenstein, surrounded by a cloud of melancholy that purportedly
makes pleasure impossible to experience, she is exploiting the logic of
her father’s commands: that is,
whatever it may do to pleasure, mightn’t it leave her free?
But
in truth, is Frankenstein really no longer happy? We note that even when
he suggests he has become such a vortex of misery that even praise has become
but another source of pain, he isn’t much averse to recounting specific
examples of this now pain-inducing praise. He recounts, for instance:
why, M.
Clerval, I assure you he [Frankenstein] has outstript us all. Ay, stare
if you please; but it is nevertheless true. A youngster who but a
few years ago, believed in Cornelius Agrippa as firmly as in the
Gospel, has now set himself at the head of the university and if he
is not soon pulled down, we shall all be out of countenance. — Ay, ay, [. .
.] Mr. Frankenstein is modest, an excellent quality in a young man.
Young men should be diffident of themselves, you know, Mr. Clerval; I was
myself when young, but that wears out in a very short time. (66)
Frankenstein
would have us believe he experiences little pleasure in, not only such high
praise, but high praise from one who does not believe great accomplishments are
necessarily also immodest ones.
Frankenstein
continues to astonish people until his death. We remember Walton’s
“astonishment on hearing such a question addressed to [him] [. . .] from a man
on the brink of destruction” (24). And though some doubt whether Walton
is a trustworthy narrator, I think his assessment of Frankenstein on the mark
when he concludes: “Such a man has a double existence: he may suffer
misery and be overwhelmed by disappointments, yet, when he has retired into
himself, he will be like a celestial spirit, that has a halo around him, within
whose circle no grief or folly ventures” (28). Shelley, through
Frankenstein, has offered herself a sort of self-acceptance for her own
consideration, where, though it amounts to internalizing badness, also means to
no longer be at war with oneself. It does not amount to stasis; in fact,
just the opposite—it offers the potential to change, to evolve, precisely
because it helps resolve inhibiting inner-conflicts. Frankenstein is not
consistently at peace; he still suffers grief and experiences misery. But as Walton observes, he now has the
ability to recover and continue on his way. Yes, I know—Frankenstein perishes along the way. But does this represent proof, for
Shelley, of the trueness of the moral of the story? Or, having used Frankenstein to achieve for herself a kind
of solution, does satisfaction from discovery now replace the energy of the
inner-toil that drove the writing of the book, the telling of the tale, making
it simply the appropriate time to leave her proxy behind and put down the pen?
Silly
consideration? Consider how many people find strange the ending of Huckleberry Finn in which, after a
confrontation with God we intuitively felt the book was leading to, Huck is
more or less abandoned as the main protagonist as he but passively participates
in what really amounts to the further adventures of Tom Sawyer. Both
Twain and Shelley were using their characters for their own crucial psychic
explorations, and when they create a situation for their protagonists—for
themselves—that manifests a “solution,” a way out/through, it’s time to
distance themselves from the creation, either by ending the book or through the
insertion of some other protagonist (one who does not so closely resemble
themselves) to carry out the remainder of the action. The mind primarily
busies itself in its hoarding away of the long-sought discovery for subsequent
picking-ats and unraveling.
Wendy
Steiner, in an introduction to Frankenstein,
newly released as one of the Modern Library Paperback Classics, believes
Frankenstein’s polar adventure does not offer Frankenstein transcendence.
She argues, instead, that the ending amounts to a critique by Mary Shelley of
the sublime:
The
sublime takes individuals out of their time and place and lifts them into what
Mary Shelley portrays as a deathly, inhuman transcendence. Of course, in
Kant and Burke, this liberation from the here and now is the supreme
achievement of the imagination, but it is clear that Mary Shelley
disagreed. Frankenstein spends most of his time in the Alps or on the
polar ice cap, the archetypal landscapes of the sublime; by contrast the Rhine
Valley, where he travels with Henry, is a romantic setting of gentler
beauty. “The mountains of Switzerland,” he says, “are more majestic and
strange, but there is a charm in the banks of this divine river that I never
before saw equalled.” “Charm” is a term that Kant slightingly associates with
“the agreeable”—meretricious beauty, sentiment, the allure of surfaces.
If Frankenstein’s pure taste craves the self-annihilating sublime, Mary
Shelley’s belief in “the amiableness of domestic affection, and the excellence
of universal virtue” finds its analogue in the aesthetic of Charm. (xix)
Frankenstein
tries to make a firm distinction between the sublime and the picturesque, and
perhaps this helped fool Steiner, because “the amiableness of domestic
affection” most certainly does
surface when Frankenstein is in the Alps! Traveling through the valley of
Chamounix, Frankenstein observes that though “this valley is more wonderful and
sublime, [it is] [. . .] no[t] so beautiful and picturesque, as that of Servox”
(91); but of the entire journey of the Alps, including traveling through the
“high and snowy mountains [. . .] and beholding the “supreme and magnificent
Mont Blanc” (92), Frankenstein tells us:
A
tingling log-lost sense of pleasure often came across me during this
journey. Some turn in the road, some new object suddenly perceived and
recognised, reminded me of days gone by, and were associated with the
light-hearted gaiety of boyhood. The very winds whispered in soothing accents,
and maternal nature bade me weep no more. [. . .] [W]atching the pallid
lightnings that played above Mont Blanc, and listening to the rushing of
the Arve [,] [. . .] the same lulling sounds acted as a lullaby to my too keen
sensations. (92)
Mont
Blanc is itself cuddled by the “vast river of ice [which] [. . .] wound
among its dependent mountains” (95). I do not believe being reminded of
the “light-hearted gaiety of boyhood” is what Steiner is alluding to in her
argument that the sublime brings about thoughts of transcendence from the here
and now, and I doubt that Shelley could imagine any landscape more soothing,
more gentle, than Frankenstein’s description of the Alps allows. It certainly does not seem a deathly or
inhuman sort of transcendence, either. And indisputably there is much
more a sense of cocooning in this passage than any move toward
self-annihilation. No, Shelley is not criticizing the sublime landscape
here; and the key word is not “charm” but rather “joy”—joy in nature offering,
after travels in any region,
serenity, fulfillment.
Joy
comes in his contemplations of nature, whether the Rhine, the Alps, or a sea of
polar ice. About the northern ocean
of ice, Frankenstein remarks:
The
Greeks wept for joy when they beheld the Mediterranean from the hills of Asia,
and hailed with rapture the boundary of their toils. I did not weep, but
I knelt down, and, with a full heart, thanked my guiding spirit for conducting
me in safety to the place where I hoped, notwithstanding my adversary’s give,
to meet and grapple with him. (199)
This
thanking of spirits for the chance to grapple with his creation is not evidence
of his madness; instead, it is the very real pleasure Frankenstein is capable
of feeling, now that he has decided he will confront rather than be intimidated
by the demands of his confessor. He dies before he has the chance, but
the monster gives what amounts to a fair account of Frankenstein’s and
Shelley’s strange but real triumph: “Yet when she died!—nay, then I was
not miserable. I had cast off all feeling, subdued all anguish, to riot
in the excess of my despair. Evil thenceforth became my good”
(212).
Steiner
is right, though, to describe “the plot of Frankenstein
[as] [. . .] a demonic parody of the epiphanic ‘spots of time,’ in Wordsworth’s
‘Prelude.’ Every episode in the novel is the same trauma, nightmarishly
repeated: the loss of a loved one”
(xix). Where I differ with him is in believing that the purpose of the
repetition is not to draw attention to, to emphasize, the consequences of
hubris—to offer the same moral lesson over and over again—but rather to assist
Shelley in a search for a solution to a traumatizing abandonment when for her
all pleasure turned to pain. The solution is not readily grasped; it
requires wide knowledge of the way people work along with the capacity to
accept some unsettling truths. But
it is a Romantic one (where “Evil thenceforth became my good” [212]) that
rivals the oddity and remarkableness of Keats’ own solution to a similar
moment in his own life he too cannot but obsess over.
Before
arriving at a better solution, Shelley has Frankenstein satisfy himself with
moments where “a truce [is] [. . .] established between the present hour and
the irresistible, disastrous future” (178). I believe this is the
satisfaction Keats experiences from contemplating the urn. I mentioned
earlier that the onset of dating often brings about parental rejection. The reason is because dating, like
motherhood, means making someone other than your parents the primary focus of
your concerns. In Frankenstein,
the father tells Frankenstein to turn his attention to his family when he
experiences self-pleasure, and we learn from Hill-Miller that Shelley’s father
was greatly displeased with her daughter’s decision to elope with Percy
Shelley. In “Ode to a Grecian Urn”
we have two lovers “frozen” just as they are about to kiss (“[t]hough winning
near the goal”[18]). This image is followed by one of townsfolk coming to
sacrifice. Together, they constitute a before and after—or more aptly, an
if/then: if you choose to embrace,
then you can expect to be promptly punished for doing so. By being frozen in time, the lovers are
saved, not simply from experiencing their own sure inconstancy in love and the
slow effects of aging on young beauty but from the community’s hard judgment
that was to follow their rapturous union.
The
poem’s structure pits the ideals and strivings of youth against the harsh
judgments of parents. It begins with the narrator, excited by what he
sees on the urn, eagerly asking questions: “What men or gods are
these? What maidens loath? / What mad pursuit? What
struggle to escape? What pipes and timbrels? What wild ecstasy?”
(8-10). He, like Walton in Frankenstein,
is “by [his] [. . .] eagerness and
[. . .] wonder and hope [. . .] express[ing] [. . .] that [he] expect[s] to be
informed of the secret with which [the urn is] [. . .] acquainted” (51).
We remember Frankenstein refusing to “lead [Walton] [. . .] on to [his] [. . .]
destruction and infallible misery” (51-52), his lecturing him on “how much
happier that man is who believes his native town to be the world, than he who
aspires to become greater than his nature will allow” (52). Similarly,
the urn, in a sense, attempts to stop the narrator’s over-eager and perilous
investigations, supposedly “out of friendship,” as “a friend to man” (48),
moralizing “Beauty is truth, truth beauty,”—that is all / Ye know on
earth, and all ye need to know” (49-50).
These
last two lines are as famous as near any out of Shakespeare. They last
because they pointedly and (brilliantly) poetically represent the inhibiting
voice of our parents—the power similar voiced statements have had in faithfully
inhibiting generation after generation of youth from realizing their full
potential. Some critics believe
they represent Keats’ firmly held conclusions, having arisen from his own
investigations of truths for man (Lyon 45). Sidney Colvin says
that “amidst the gropings of reason and the flux of things, [truth is
beauty, beauty is truth] is to the poet and artist—at least to one of Keats’
temper—an immutable law” (45).
Others have an adverse reaction to them, believing they are poetically
jolting, or self-evidently false, or the voice of the urn rather than Keats’
own.
William
Wilkinson believes that the “idea of ‘truth’ [is] [. . .] foisted in with
violence” (49), and that it upsets both the beauty and believability of the
poem. He proceeds to create a “better” ending where “[b]eauty is joy”
(49). H. W. Garrod believes that “every reader [. . .] in some degree
feels them, feels a certain uneasiness [in the last two lines]” (60).
Royall Snow damns the message: “[t]hat is nonsense and instinctively we
feel it. The poem is so well loved precisely because that appeal is valid and universal. Though we
crave a solution of the questions transiency
raises in our minds, we scarcely crave this
solution once its implications become clear” (62). Snow investigates
whether it is possible that “Keats never either meant nor made such a statement
as ‘Beauty is truth?’” (62). He concludes that he did not; the trouble is
that the message has been taken out of context. Snow, though, believes
there is a consistent single voice encountered throughout the poem. Like
F.R. Leavis, he believes “[t]he proposition is strictly in keeping with the
attitude concretely embodied in the poem” (78). Others find the riddle
solved upon appreciating that they are “uttered by the urn without any
interference on the part of the poet” (Lyon 111).
The
mere fact that there are a variety of opinions here is refreshing compared with
the near absence of mental-wrestling over whether or not Frankenstein’s
moralizing statement to Walton is in fact a component of Shelley’s own
world-view. The best we get there is the suggestion that Shelley’s
warning, “however reasoned and erudite [,] [. . .] has sounded timid next to
the heroes challenge of Frankensteinian inquiry, and posterity has preferred
horror over healing” (Steiner xx). In short, most critics do not explore
as they do with Keats’ “Ode to a Grecian Urn,” whether the moralizing voice is not in fact the voice of the
writer. Neither work is simply the
playing out of a conclusion regarding life either writer has already arrived
at, however. Instead, both are
active working-outs of a life experience that afflicts them enough for them to
attempt to find a solution through their
writing of the work itself.
In
both works there is the staging of the warring elements—youthful ambition
versus parental intimidation.
Shelley uses the pursuit of youthful studies to taste success; Keats
uses the young lovers to know love. Concerning Keats, Clarence Thorpe
concurs:
[T]he
symbols executed here, themselves a product of mind and soul, still contain
within themselves a dynamic something that has power to kindle the imagination
of a sympathetic observer, who [. . .] is able to re-create the
particular bits of life[.] [T]he image [of the young lovers] comes to the
mind of Keats in a pleasurable wave of recognition. It is pleasurable
because he detects, starting out at him from the fair chiselled form,
waves of intuitive whisperings that seize his imagination and set it aflame[.]
(58-59)
I differ
from Thorpe in believing that what the “kindl[ing] the imagination” (59) of a
sympathetic observer amounts to is a merging with the image, not simply being stimulated by it, so to become a near participant in the scene, and that the
pleasurable wave of recognition is not caught sight of a semblance to one’s own
experiences but the result of a more direct re-experiencing of the past.
The
critic I am in most sympathy with in regards to its meaning agrees that the
poem represents, though disguised, a moment from Keats’ own past. Albert
Mordell believes that “emotions connected with Fanny Brawne [Keats’ former
lover] inspired his two most famous odes [,] [including] [. . .] ‘to the
Grecian Urn’” (199). “Keats saw a resemblance between himself and that
youth. He, too, was winning and near the goal, and he no more had her
love than did the youth on the urn. [. . .] He had to accept his lot and
pretend to see some advantage in it as he did in that of the youth on the urn”
(205). Compromise owes to his sharing a fate akin to Frankenstein’s,
when, even when he “appeared almost within grasp of [his] [. . .] foe, [he had
his] [. . .] hopes [. . .] suddenly extinguished” (201). Consummation,
experience of any moment that would make one truly happy, is often one where
pleasure turns into pain. Branden
notes that “[he] had the opportunity to work with many thousands of people in a
variety of professional contexts and settings[,] [and] [. . .] is absolutely
persuaded that happiness anxiety is one of our most widespread and least
understood problems” (91). He continues:
Many
people feel they do not deserve happiness, are not entitled to happiness, have
no right to the fulfillment of their emotional needs and wants. Often
they feel that if they are happy, either their happiness will be taken away
from them, or something terrible will happen to counterbalance it, some
unspeakable punishment or tragedy. (97)
Branden
notes that to stop and reflect on one’s troubles, in an effort to properly
identify and resolve them, is unusual, because most people fear that if they
ever stop and look inside they may discover “there’s nothing there” (93).
Rather than reflect upon and attempt to resolve it, most often when feeling
anxious, “[i]n order to make it more bearable, it is commonly converted into
specific, tangible fears, which might seem to have some semblance of
plausibility of the circumstances of one’s life [but which amount to] [. . .] a
smokescreen and defence against an anxiety whose roots lie in the core
experience of self” (79). Keats is
using the two lovers to engage his past.
In this he is already somewhat less the coward than Mordell assesses him
as.
It
is true, though, that Keats, like Shelley, is imagining what it might feel like
if he pretended it true that “Heard melodies are sweet, but those unheard
/ Are sweeter” (11-12). He is trying the rationalization on, just as
Shelley is trying on the idea that it is best to live modestly, quietly,
amongst friends and family in her native town. Both, though, have too
high a self-esteem to long content themselves with compromised offerings, for:
one of
the characteristics of high self-esteem is an eagerness for the new and the
challenging, for that which will allow an individual to use his or her
capacities to the fullest extent—just as a fondness for the familiar, the
routine, and the unexacting coupled with a fear of the new and the difficult is
a virtually unmistakable indication of low self-esteem. (Branden 90)
We have
discussed Shelley’s eventual solution, and we will soon discuss Keats’ own, but
first I will offer a brief explanation as to why we should imagine the image of
the village sacrifice as conjoined to
the image of the young lovers, not as separate and distinct from them.
The
poem, of course, begins with talk of pursuits, struggles to escape, along with
maidens and wild ecstasy. “Who are these coming to the sacrifice?” (31),
follows but three lines after “All breathing human passion far above” (28), so
they are, more or less, two images which flow into one another. From
“Lead’st thou that heifer lowin at the skies” (33), we know that a heifer, a
young cow, is to be sacrificed. The sacrifice of animals in antiquity was
actually a change for the better in the history of the barbaric ritual of
sacrifice; previously, sacrifices were human, healthy young men and
women—representing our most promising selves—more often than not. All we
require to understand that the heifer is in fact a metaphor for young lovers, and
that the two images are linked for Keats’ consideration of the troubling
moments in his past when pleasure turned to pain, is to understand that dating
often leads to parental rejection; children, who initially worship their
parents as gods, and imagine their family as all the world, are left alone to
contend with the wiles of the world—are
sacrificed—by their parents, as they begin to focus more on themselves and
life beyond the home.
Keats’
“Ode to Melancholy” represents his own Romantic solution to the terror and pain
of parental rejection. Rather than acquiesce to parents’
demands, Keats offers a prescription for continuing on in the very teeth
of pain, making a poem that begins with “death moths” (6) and “mournful Psyche”
(7) rather than with a “flowery tale” (4) and a “wild ecstasy” (10), actually
the more uplifting of the two poems. If all great pleasures turn into
piercing pain, if “Joy [. . .] Turn[s] [. . .] to Poison while the bee-mouth
sips” (24), there is another option available other than avoiding vivid
experience in ostensible preference for “unheard melodies”: keep sipping. To prescribe
feeding “deep, deep upon [the] [. . .] peerless eyes” (20) of melancholy
amounts in my mind to an admission that “heard” melodies are in fact much sweeter than “unheard” ones, they just come with
the bitterest of after-tastes. Same thing also, with unconsummated
love. Keats concludes that it is better to suffer the pain than otherwise
because otherwise “For shade to shade will come too drowsily” (9): our experiences in life will be muted
ones. As Morris Dickstein tells
us, the “permanence that the [. . .] Grecian urn seemed to offer is forgotten
[. . .]. Keats no longer seeks passive dissolution, freedom from the flux
and tension of actuality; he dismisses that wish, demands passionate assault on
the world of experience, with all its contrary sensations, with all its
intimations of mortality” (231).
This
is the declaration of a Romantic.
In a sense, it is not dissimilar to what Frankenstein’s family had hoped
Justine capable of. They believed it better to resist “confessors,” to
resist being compliant, for, even if this leads to torture, to “let[ting] her
[confessors] rave” (19), in addition to being both good and right it also
affords a pleasing sense of self-regard that counts against the pain. Keats is choosing not to follow the path of least resistance, which would have him,
not drink down terrors but douse his anxieties with drugs in some effort to
turn them off. Instead, he declares he will continue to imbibe them so he
might enjoy a rich, resonate life.
John
Keats died at an early age and so we are used to hearing that “[n]o one can
read Keats’ poems and letters without an undersense of immense waste of so
extraordinary an intellect and genius cut off so early” (Abrams 504). One
rarely encounters such regret for Frankenstein, for, for his hubris of
self-attendance and transgressive exploits, he ostensibly deserved no
better. But in coming to this conclusion, a conclusion I believe Mary
Shelley herself did not subscribe to and was struggling the whole of her life
to resist, are we rewarding ourselves with the sense of superiority that comes
from being good at the expense of the genuine superiority that could follow
from our being bad? Is it really
true that happiness and self-respect lie in never forgetting all our parents
are due, in moderating our pleasures in deference to all we have been told we
still owe them? Or is this a
deception we foist on ourselves, a “truth” we feel we must try to oblige, lest
we slip into self-condemnation, self-hatred? Mightn’t it be, that is, that we just failed where others
would have succeeded?
Works
Cited
Abrams,
M.H. (general editor). The Norton
Anthology of English Literature Vol. 2. New York: Norton, 1968. Print.
Branden, Nathaniel. Honoring the Self: The Psychology of Confidence and Respect. Bantam, 1985. Print.
Damrosch,
David (general editor). The Longman Anthology of British Literature Vol. 2. New York: Addison-Wesley, 1999.
Print.
DeMause,
Lloyd. “Childhood and Cultural Evolution.” Emotional
Life of Nations. Institute of Psychohistory. Web.
Dickstein,
Morris. Keats and His Poetry: A Study in
Development. Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 1971. Print.
Hill-Miller,
Katherine. “My Hideous Progeny”: Mary
Shelley, William Godwin, and the Father-Daughter Relationship. Newark: U of
Delaware P, 1995. Print.
Hindle,
Maurice. Introduction. Frankenstein or
the Modern Prometheus. By Mary Shelley. New York: Penguin, 1992. Print.
Mordell,
Albert. The Erotic Motive in Literature.
New York: Boni and Liveright, 1919. Print.
Lyon,
Harvey ed. Keats’ Well-Read Urn: An
Introduction to Literary Method. New York: Holt, 1958. Print.
Mellor, Anne. Mary
Shelley: Her Life, Her Fiction, Her Monsters. New York: Routledge, 1988. Print.
Shelley, Mary. Frankenstein
or the Modern Prometheus. New York: Penguin,
1992. Print.
Shelley, Mary. Frankenstein
or the Modern Prometheus. New York: Modern Library,
1999. Print.
Steiner. Wendy. Introduction. Frankenstein or the Modern Prometheus. By
Mary Shelley. New York: Modern
Library, 1999. Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment