The Apology, Aristotle
Reviewed
by Patrick McEvoy-Halston
- -
- - -
Socrates
and his God
May 2004
Given what we hear from him in The Apology, it is not clear why Socrates “follows” his God,
Apollo. There is evidence to
support three explanations: 1)
because he is compelled to; 2) because he wants to enable goodness; and 3) out
of self-interest.
At
least in The Apology, Socrates never
says he “follows” God. Instead, he
characterizes himself as God’s gift to the Athenians. He says, “I am really one given to you by God” (437), and as
such he is not so much someone who follows Him as he is an extension or a key
possession of His. He argues that
it is because he is a gift of God’s that he possesses a capacity to neglect “all
[his] [. . .] own interests” (437), and why an affront to him amounts to an
offence against his god. It is a
self-conception that makes him seem most like a puppet, most like someone who
follows God because He is, so to speak, pulling his strings, and explains why
he argues that he “cannot” “disobey
the god” (443; emphasis added).
But
there is also evidence in “the Apology” to support understanding him as not
compelled to follow God but as drawn
to follow Him. When Socrates says
that through “oracles and dreams” (439) his “God commands” him “to wake [. . .]
up” (436) his fellow Athenians, when he says that he was “posted” by God with a
specific “duty to be a philosopher” (434-35), we sense he feels strongly
obligated but not compelled to follow his god’s plans for him. The prophetic voice he hears “checks”
him, it “opposes” (445) him. It is
or has an “influence” (439) he strongly registers and which impedes his
actions, but is not unequivocally presented as something which cannot be resisted. That is, we are left room to believe
the primary reason he heeds its directions is because he “trust[s]” (441) its
source, Apollo. He trusts Apollo
because he believes Him “wise” (429) and good. Alone, though like everyone he would want to be good, he
would never be sure what goodness was; but following the directions of his god
makes him sure “there is no greater good for [his fellow Athenians] [. . .] in
the city in any way than [his] [. . .] service to God” (436).
But
his defence also provides evidence for understanding Socrates as following his
god because servility has its (considerable) benefits. Socrates argues that following His
commands has meant an arduous life, but also a life of hearing from a “familiar
prophetic voice [. . .] even in very small things” (445). Unlike Oedipus, who felt abandoned by
the gods, Socrates keeps constant company with his—a god, who, yes, commands
him to live a life which leaves him materially poor, but one who also leaves
him feeling certain he is important both to Him and to most important
Athenians. Socrates suggests he
has little or rather no interest in “title[s]” (429) or honor, but if we doubt
his sincerity, he would have had to have done more than just point to his material poverty to prove he does not
follow his god for riches.
Socrates
may not be proud or self-interested, but we know that even if he was he would
be very unlikely to admit this to himself, for he has much riding on his being
thought good by his god. Socrates
playfully imagines spending his time joyfully conversing with heroes such as
Odysseus in his afterlife. He says
that only God knows what awaits him after death; but the reason he might be
thinking of an ideal ultimate fate for himself is because he feels sure “no
evil can happen to a good man either living or dead, and his business is not
neglected by the gods” (446).
We
have evidence, then, to support several hypotheses as to why Socrates “follows”
his god. Socrates would disavow the latter, and possibly the latter two, but
all three explanations are backed by
evidence. We might at least agree
that Socrates follows God because he believes gods exist whom one might
follow—but his accusers are given reason in The
Apology to consider otherwise.
Socrates constantly refers to his god in his defence, but one of the
reasons he is on trial is because he is accused of being a dangerous
atheist. In this position, a
self-preserving atheist as much as a reverent follower of God, would be sure to
intersperse his defence with references to Him.
Work
Cited
Aristotle. The Philosophy of Aristotle. Comp. Renford Bambrough. Eds. J.L.
Creed and A.E. Wardman. New York: Signet, 2003.
No comments:
Post a Comment